Socrates

By A. E. Taylor








Chapter I. Introductory

The life of a great man, particularly when he belongs to a remote age, can never be a mere record of undisputed fact. Even when such facts are plentiful, the biographer’s real business is with their interpretation; he must penetrate behind mere events to the purpose and character they disclose, and can only do so by an effort of constructive imagination. And in the case of both the historical figures whose influence on the life of humanity has been profoundest, Jesus and Socrates, indisputable facts are exceptionally rare; perhaps there is only one statement about each which a man might not deny without forfeiting his claim to be counted among the sane. It is certain that Jesus ‘suffered under Pontius Pilate,’ and no less certain that Socrates was put to death at Athens on a charge of impiety in the ‘year of Laches’ (399 B.C.). Any account of either which goes beyond such a statement is inevitably |10| a personal construction. Hence even this unpretentious sketch must be introduced by some remarks on the sources from which its writer has drawn the materials of his own construction, and the principles which have guided him in his use of them.


“Plato’s Socrates is a humorist and a great philosopher, with
profound metaphysical convictions and a wide acquaintance
with the highest science of his time.”


Socrates himself left no record of his own thought or actions. That he did not is a direct consequence of the character of the society to which he belonged. Though the part of his life of which we know most, his old age, was prolonged into a different and less happy time, Socrates was, by birth and upbringing, a man of the great age of Pericles; in fact, he was a man of over forty at the death of that statesman. Now the Athenians of those spacious days did not write books; it was an age of great tragedies, but not of prose literature. This is why, apart from one single instructive, but not absolutely certain, allusion, we have no contemporary record of anything done or said by Socrates until he was close on fifty. He was already forty-seven or more when the famous comic poets, Aristophanes and Amipsias, for some reason both selected him as the butt of their topical burlesques for the year 423 B.C.; a third comedian, Eupolis, followed suit |11| two years later. We still possess Aristophanes’ brilliant caricature, the Clouds, though in a version perhaps retouched by the author, and it is the only document dealing with Socrates which dates from a time before his own death.

The deep impression made by the trial and death of the philosopher led at once to the creation of a whole literature in which younger men who had come under his influence sought to preserve his memory by depicting his personality and conversation. Much of this has perished, but we still have the imposing series of dialogues in which Plato has made Socrates the central figure, the apologetic Memorials of the Master composed by Xenophon, with one or two minor works of the same kind from his hand, and a few pages of the Socratic dialogues of a third contemporary, Aeschines of Sphettus, and these, of course, are the main sources for any account of the philosopher. The problem is to know the right way to handle them. It is important to remember that all three writers were many years the juniors of their hero. Plato was some forty-three years younger than Socrates, Xenophon almost certainly a few years younger still, and though we have no exact dates for |12| Aeschines, he must be roughly contemporary with the others.1

None of the three, then, can have had trustworthy recollections of Socrates as he was before the age of fifty-five; when they tell us anything of his prime, or his early life, they are not speaking from first-hand knowledge.2

Biography as a recognized form of literature only appears among the Greeks in the third |13| century B.C. (300-200 B.C.) as characteristic of the Alexandrian age. Philosophers, like poets, had by that time become objects of curiosity to a reading public, and more than one writer set himself to gratify this curiosity. The works thus produced have perished, but their substance is preserved for us in the Lives of Philosophers, which bears the otherwise unknown name of Diogenes Laertius, and, in its final form, dates from about A.D. 200. The account given of Socrates in this work remains as the chief monument of what was known or surmised about its subject by men of letters living under the Ptolemies and later. Of course it has preserved some statements of great value, substantiated by the names of the earlier authors who vouch for them. But the critical standard of the biographers of the Alexandrian age was not high. Their public demanded not so much accuracy as piquant anecdote, scandal, and repartee, and the writer had to study the taste of his public. Moreover, an author of this age was not very favourably placed for ascertaining the facts about the career of a fifth-century Athenian. The material was scanty, and consisted largely of unexplained passing allusions, often enough of topical jests |14| in some comedy, the meaning of which was as obscure to an Alexandrian as it is to us. Biographies compiled under such conditions must not be expected to throw much light on the personality of any one, least of all on that of a man who, like Dr. Johnson, was already becoming the centre of a legend in his own lifetime. Thus for serious purposes we are thrown back almost entirely upon what we are told about Socrates by persons who could speak from their own direct knowledge, that is, in the main, upon Aristophanes, Plato, and Xenophon.

How far can we trust the representations of any or all of these writers? If certain theories widely held in the nineteenth century are sound, it would be rash to trust any of them. Aristophanes, it was said, is a comic poet, and his business is not to tell the truth but to distort it. The differences between his Socrates and those of Xenophon and Plato are so marked that we cannot take them for portraits of a single original. Either the poet and his audience must have known nothing about the ostensible hero of his play, or his object must have been something different from effective personal caricature. His satire must be pointed not at an individual but at a ‘movement’ |15| and we must take his Socrates, like Moliere’s Tartuffe, to be no more than an imaginary type, to which he has tacked the name of a particular contemporary as a label without troubling himself about the justice of the selection. Plato, no doubt, had the intimate knowledge and the dramatic gifts which might have enabled him to draw a faithful and vivid picture. But his purpose, it was generally held, was not that of the portrait-painter. His Socrates was meant either as a fancy picture of what a great philosopher should be, or as a ‘mask’ for himself. This was supposed to be proved by alleged discrepancies between Plato’s account and Xenophon’s. The Socrates of Xenophon is an excellent, but rather prosy, preacher of a good, common-sense morality, with a marked dislike of unpractical speculations and ‘useless’ science.3 Plato’s is a humorist and a great philosopher, with profound metaphysical convictions and a wide acquaintance with the highest science of his time. Hence it was assumed that the genius, the humour, the metaphysics, have been imported |16| into the picture by Plato; they are disguised self-revelation.4 It was inferred at first that the true way to get at the historical facts about Socrates is to pin our faith to Xenophon and use his statements to reduce the great figure of the Platonic dialogues to conventional proportions. (The ‘historical Socrates’ of whom nineteenth-century writers had much to say, meant, in fact, the Socrates of Plato with the genius taken out of him.) On further inquiry, however, it appears that there are good reasons for being uneasy about the competence of Xenophon himself as a witness. It does not appear from his own writings that he was ever particularly intimate with Socrates, and it seems to be certain that he cannot have been more than twenty-four at the outside when he saw the Master for the last time.5 |17| In any case, he was far away in Asia when Socrates was tried and condemned, and his own Socratic writings must have been composed at various intervals after his subsequent return to Greece, when he was living in exile from Athens and without much opportunity of consulting other surviving members of the Socratic circle. In some of them he tries our belief hard by attributing to the notoriously town-loving Socrates his own marked taste for farming and country life, and the most considerable of them, the Memorabilia, is further put out of count to an unknown extent by the fact that it has an avowedly ‘apologetic’ purpose. It is also pointed out that there is good reason to think that Xenophon has eked out his own, probably not very extensive, |18| recollections by using as material for his picture the very Platonic dialogues which he was at one time used to ‘control.’ This explains why there was a tendency among many of the foremost scholars at the opening of the present century to complete scepticism about the very possibility of any knowledge of the ‘historical Socrates.’6 An agnosticism of this kind must always be a melancholy pis aller for the historian; in the case of Socrates there is fortunately a way out of it, if we are careful to interpret our evidence in the light of certain sound general principles.


“Aristophanes represents Socrates as the head of a regular ‘School’ who combines physical science with what we should call ‘spiritualism.’”


To begin with the question of the worth of the testimony of Aristophanes and his brother |19| comedians. We have in the first place to remember that the Old Attic Comedy dealt throughout in personal burlesque, not in satire on generalized social ‘types,’ and that it was essential to the comedian’s success that the object of the burlesque should be a public notoriety. We may therefore be perfectly certain that Socrates was already a well-known figure when Aristophanes attacked him, and that the poet counted upon the excellence of the caricature as something which the audience would recognize. Also we have to remember the general principle that a successful burlesque must be founded on notorious fact, or what is believed to be such.7 It must be a distortion, for comic effect, of something which is not the mere invention of the caricaturist. Consequently, when Aristophanes makes it the main point of his play to represent Socrates as the head of something like a regular ‘School’ who combine physical science with what we should call ‘spiritualism,’ though we should be |20| very foolish if we took his representations at anything like their ‘face value.’ we should be equally foolish not to ask ourselves what are the real facts which explain the caricature, and whether we cannot discern them reappearing from a different angle of vision in what we are told by Plato or Xenophon.

It is true, again, that there is a marked contrast between the Socrates of the Aristophanic play, with his ‘pupils’ and ‘thinking-shop,’ and the Platonic (or Xenophontic) Socrates with his ‘mission’ to every one who will listen to him. But when we remember that Aristophanes is burlesquing Socrates as he was, or was believed to be, at a time when Plato and Xenophon were little more than babies, we should see that the contrast may well be largely explained by this difference in date. It may prove to be the fact that Socrates at forty-five was in some ways a different man from Socrates at fifty-five or sixty, and that evidence of the fact is actually supplied by the works of Plato and Xenophon themselves, when we read them with proper attention. I shall accordingly make use, for the purpose of this sketch, of the evidence of Attic comedy, though, I hope, always with due caution. |21|

When we come to consider the real or alleged discrepancies between Plato and Xenophon themselves, the first thing that is likely to strike us is that they have often been unduly exaggerated. Except on one or two points of detail, Xenophon does not formally contradict anything which Plato tells us about Socrates. What he does is to leave things out, or to reduce them to the level of the commonplace. The range of information with which he supplies us is limited. It is possible, using Plato alone, to compile a rather full biography of his hero, from early manhood to the last years; it would be quite impossible to construct any such narrative from the much more meagre information supplied by Xenophon,8 though careful reading will often show us that he incidentally confirms some of Plato’s most characteristic assertions. Again, the vivid individuality of Plato’s portrait of Socrates is all but entirely lost in Xenophon, who ignores most of the peculiarities which make Plato’s hero an ‘original.’ The ‘irony,’ or peculiar humour, of Socrates, for example, and his |22| characteristic attitude of ‘Socratic doubt’ are both known to us exclusively from Plato; Xenophon’s Socrates has no doubts about anything and no humour to speak of. Now it is, of course, a possible explanation of this that Socrates was a commonplace person whom Plato has converted into a first-rate figure by crediting him with a personality which really belongs to Plato himself.9 But it is also an equally possible hypothesis that the actual man Socrates had the marvellous endowments Plato ascribes to him, and that their absence from the slighter sketch of Xenophon is due to imperfect insight, or lack of dramatic power in the author. The commonplace personality may be that of the writer, not that of his subject.


“Xenophon does not formally contradict anything Plato tells us about Socrates. He does leave things out, or reduce them to the level of the commonplace.”


We have also to bear in mind that the avowed purpose of Xenophon’s Memorials requires him to present Socrates in a commonplace light. Though the book lacks thorough-going unity of design, and was clearly composed piecemeal, its general character is determined by |23| the fact that it opens as a formal apology, or defence, for Socrates against the charges made against him at his trial. Xenophon’s object is to argue that, on their own premisses, the dicasts who found Socrates guilty of irreligion and misleading ‘the young’ were making a mistake; he was really a model of all that his prosecutors themselves understood by piety, and the morality he practised and inculcated was exactly what the ordinary good Athenian citizen would desire to exhibit in his own life and impress on his sons, if he could. Now it is, of course, clear, as Burnet has said, that such a defence fails precisely because it is too successful; if Socrates had been what Xenophon wants us to believe, he would never have been prosecuted. Xenophon’s apologetic purpose absolutely requires him to suppress, as far as he can, any feature in the character of his hero which is original, and therefore disconcerting to a dull and conventionally-minded reader. It follows that in reading his narrative we must never forget the principle, which applies to all polemic of this kind, that the most valuable statements of the apologist are just those incidental admissions which are incompatible with the case he is putting forward. For example, |24| Xenophon is damaging his own case when he incidentally betrays in one passage the fact that Socrates had at some date been something very like the head of a group of scientific students (Memorabilia, I. vi. 14), in another that he possessed advanced knowledge of geometry and astronomy (Memorabilia, IV. vii. 2-6), and in a third that foreign Pythagoreans were among his intimate associates (Memorabilia, I. ii. 48); and this gives a peculiar significance to his evidence on all these points. Even if we suppose that Xenophon is here drawing upon Platonic dialogues such as the Phaedo, which he had certainly read, that he should do so is proof that he found Plato’s representations consistent with what he knew of Socrates. If we read Xenophon in the light of the cautions just given, I believe it will be found that his account of the philosopher nowhere seriously contradicts the fuller Platonic narrative, and at times confirms it in a remarkable way.

We still have to face the main objection which has been brought against the Platonic dialogues as a faithful representation of the life and thought of a real historical person. It is clear that without Plato we have no material for a connected biography of Socrates which will throw any light |25| on his personality; it is also true that Plato offers us a very full, vivid, and internally consistent picture of the central personage of his dialogues. But this, of itself, does not prove that Plato’s Socrates may not be, from first to last, a product of the creative imagination, like Othello or Falstaff, and it is still held in many quarters, though not so confidently as it was held fifty years ago, that he is this. Can we give any sufficient reason for rejecting this once generally accepted belief? To argue the point exhaustively would require an entire volume, but I may indicate here the main considerations which seem to my own mind decisive.10

In the first place, the minute researches of scholars of the last fifty or sixty years, Lewis Campbell, C. Ritter, Lutoslawski, and others, |26| have definitely proved that a certain group of important Platonic dialogues (Sophistes, Politicus, Philebus, Timaeus, Laws), with marked peculiarities of vocabulary and style, must be later than the rest of the philosopher’s writings, and clearly belong to an advanced period of his life in which he was the head of an organized school with a very definite doctrine of its own. It is clear that these works were written at a much later period of life than the great mass of Plato’s dialogues, and among this larger mass there are one or two, Republic, Phaedrus, Theaetetus, which seem to be, in point of style, transitional. There is consequently a general consensus of scholars that the greater number of the Platonic dialogues must have been composed before Plato had definitely founded his school, the Academy; the Sophistes-Laws group after the Academy had definitely established itself as an organized institution; the works of the transitional period either about the time of its first foundation or during the first decades of its existence.11 Now, |27| whereas in all earlier dialogues Socrates is always the central figure and the leader of discussion, we find that this is completely changed in the group which opens with the Sophistes. In only one of these latest dialogues (the Philebus, which discusses questions of ethics and moral psychology) is Socrates the leading person. In the Sophistes, Politicus, Timaeus he is present, but takes no part in the discussion, and in the Laws he is left out altogether. The logical and political doctrines of Sophistes and Politicus are expounded by an unnamed visitor from Elea, the physical theories of the Timaeus by an Italian Pythagorean, and the vast scheme of jurisprudence of the Laws by an anonymous Athenian. I can see no reason for this remarkable change of method but that given by Burnet, that Plato’s historical sense forbade him to make Socrates the expositor of philosophical and scientific interests and doctrines which Plato |28| well knew to be his own and those of his contemporaries. Here we have, as I think, positive proof that Plato did not use the figure of Socrates as a ‘mask’ for himself or as an imaginary ideal of what ‘the philosopher’ should be. If he had done so, there is no intelligible reason why the game should not have been kept up indefinitely. We may fairly infer that Plato was at least unconscious of any departure from historical verisimilitude in the picture drawn of Socrates in the more numerous dialogues where that philosopher is the central figure.12 |29|


“Plato did not use the figure of Socrates as a ‘mask’ for himself or as an imaginary ideal of what ‘the philosopher’ should be.”


In the next place, there is one group among Plato’s early writings where any other purpose seems to be excluded, those which deal with the circumstances of the trial and death of Socrates (Euthyphro, Apology, Crito, Phaedo). The case was a cause célébre, as we can see from the strictures of Isocrates in his Busiris on the littérateur Polycrates and the pamphlet in which he presented the argument for the prosecution. It is certain that Plato’s Apology must have been circulated within a very few years of the trial, and must have been read by many of the actual judges as well as by many who had been among the audience. A misrepresentation under such conditions would have been suicidal for its author, and we should infer that the very characteristic ‘defence’ — in fact, a defiance — which Plato puts into the mouth of his Master is, in its main features, a reproduction of what was actually said. So much is, indeed, now admitted by most of the scholars whose names carry most weight (e.g. Ritter and Wilamowitz-Moellendorff). But I think, with Burnet, that we are bound in consistency to go a step further. The same considerations apply with equal force to the Phaedo, with its description of the last hours of the life of Socrates. Plato |30| tells us that he was himself absent from the scene through illness, but we know, on the testimony of one of his own personal scholars,13 that he and the other members of the Socratic circle actually passed the weeks immediately after the execution at Megara, in the company of the philosopher Euclides, who is one of the characters of the narrative. Thus there can be no doubt that Plato must have been minutely informed on the events of that memorable day by a number of eye-witnesses. It is certain also that many, if not all, of the persons introduced into the dialogue as spectators or interlocutors were living when the Phaedo was circulated (for example, Euclides himself and Simmias, one of the main interlocutors). It is inconceivable to me that Plato could have perpetuated a mystification on such a theme, even if he had wished to do so, in the face of certain detection. And unless the Phaedo is a deliberate mystification, it follows at once that its central doctrine, the so-called ‘Theory of Ideas,’ which is represented as adopted by Socrates in his youth |31| and familiar to all his auditors, really was a Socratic tenet, and is no discovery of Plato’s. If this is so, the supposed reason for believing that Plato took liberties with historical truth in these dialogues vanishes, and there is nothing to prevent us from accepting the view of them most directly suggested by their contents — that their immediate purpose is not to propound a doctrine personal to their writer, but to preserve the memory of a great thinker and of a great age which had left no literature of its own.14

The truth seems to be, in fact, that Plato, like Kant, is one of those philosophers whose most |32| characteristic personal positions are only attained in late middle age. Before he was a philosopher with a doctrine and a school of his own, he was a great dramatic artist, and used his dramatic gifts to make Socrates and his circle live for a generation to whom they would, without him, have been little more than names. When he wrote these great dramatic dialogues he had probably as yet no ‘doctrine’ of his own; by the time he had a Platonic philosophy to impart, his dramatic power had been enfeebled. We must bear in mind that Plato, to all appearance, was the inventor of the Socratic dialogue as a literary form.[15] It is not clear why he should have chosen such a method of utterance if his purpose had been primarily to inculcate his own philosophy. For that purpose, dialogues between well-known persons of a generation before the writer’s own would have been a very unsatisfactory vehicle. But if Plato’s purpose was primarily to keep alive the memory of a great man and a great age, we see at once why he chose to invent the |33| particular literary form most specially appropriate to his object.

It has been asked why Plato should have composed so many and such elaborate works if the thought enshrined in them is in all its main features that of other persons. The obvious reason is that he was living, as he well knew, in a ‘post-war’ society which had survived its own day of greatness. To recreate in imagination the chief thinker of the great days of the fifth century and the circle in which he moved was at once a duty of piety to Socrates, to the perished splendours of Athens, and incidentally to the famous Athenian family to which Plato belonged, and a refuge from the personal heart-break to which Plato’s Seventh Epistle testifies. It is too often forgotten that without the evidence of Plato’s Socratic dialogues we should really know nothing at all to speak of about the intellectual life of the sixty years or so from the repulse of Xerxes to the Peace of Nicias, just the most vital and splendid period of Attic history.16 Historians, as a matter of fact, habitually draw |34| on these dialogues for their picture of the intellectual movements of this great age, but they would lose their right to do so if Plato could be suspected of playing fast and loose with historical truth, as he is often alleged to have done in his statements about Socrates.17 A theory of his literary methods which its own adherents are constantly driven to ignore is hardly likely to be a sound one.

The assumption upon which the following account of Socrates will be based is, then, that Plato’s picture of his Master is substantially accurate, and that the information he supplies about him is intended to be taken as historical fact. It does not, of course, follow that there has been no ‘transfiguration’ of Socrates in Plato’s mind by meditation on his death as a martyr, but it does follow that any such process of idealization has been unconscious, and that there is no deliberate mystification in the dialogues. It does not follow, again, that everything Plato |35| tells us must be precise historical truth. When he is describing Socrates, as he often does, as he was in the days of his own boyhood (as in the Symposium), or even long before his own birth (as in the Parmenides), he is speaking of matters of which he could have no personal knowledge, and is liable to possible mistake about them. But we have to remember that, by his own account, members of his family, from his maternal great-grandfather, the Critias of the Timaeus, down to his uncle Charmides and his two elder brothers, had all been more or less intimate with Socrates. He would thus be in a position to be exceptionally well informed about a great deal which fell outside the range of his own memories.18 If the |36| results obtained by the use of the assumption are internally self-consistent and found to be confirmed at critical points by other evidence, we may fairly regard them as beyond reasonable doubt.

Endnotes

1^ Socrates was born in or before 469 B.C., Plato in 428/7. Xenophon in the year 401 thought himself badly handicapped by his extreme youth when chosen one of the generals of the retreating Ten Thousand (Anabasis III. i. 25). Hence he is not likely to have been born before about 426/25. Aeschines is mentioned by Plato (Apology 33e) as a young man whose father should have been called as a witness by the prosecutors of Socrates if they really believed that the philosopher had ‘corrupted’ his son. He was the only one of the three present at the death of Socrates (Phaedo 59b). Plato (ib.) was lying ill, and Xenophon absent ‘somewhere in Asia.’

2^ Thus when Plato tells us in the Theaetetus of the impression made on Socrates in the last months of his life by the youthful hero of the dialogue (afterwards the most eminent mathematician of the Academy), he is writing about matters of which he had an intimate knowledge; when he describes the meeting of Socrates in early life with Parmenides and Zeno, he is dealing with events which belong to a time more than twenty years before his own birth.

3^ We shall see, however, that the common statements on this point ignore certain very significant passages of Xenophon himself.

4^ In particular, it was held, and is still held very generally, as a sort of self-evident postulate, that the so-called ‘Theory of Ideas’ taught in the Phaedo and Republic must have been invented by Plato himself after the death of Socrates and before the composition of the Phaedo. Since the dialogue represents Socrates on the day of his death as talking of this theory as one which he has held from his early manhood, a view of this kind, if sound, would prove Plato wholly unworthy of credit in anything he tells us about Socrates.

5^ It is certain that Xenophon never saw Socrates after his own departure from Athens in 401 to join the expedition of Prince Cyrus. We do not know even that he ever revisited Athens after this before his banishment in the year 394. That he had never been very intimate with Socrates may probably be inferred from the fact that his name is never mentioned by Plato, who tells us a great deal about the members of the Socratic circle. On the other hand, Aeschines introduced into his dialogue Aspasia a Xenophon who may be our writer, though scholars have felt a difficulty about the identification. (The difficulty is that the Xenophon of Aeschines is a young married man, and that we have no evidence that our Xenophon was married at so early a date in his life.)

6^ Diels, the most eminent of them all, spoke of him as an ‘unknown x.’ (My immediate authority for this statement is an unpublished letter from Diels to a British scholar.) I do not reckon with the now exploded view that the incidental remarks of Aristotle about the thought of Socrates can be used as a ‘control’ of both Xenophon and Plato. Socrates had been dead for more than thirty years when Aristotle first came to Athens, and I think it has been demonstrated by myself and others that he says nothing of any moment about the older philosopher which he might not have learned (as I have no doubt he did) from reading the Platonic dialogues. (Cf. C. Ritter, Sokrates, p. 83.)

7^ The Clouds was not a success on the stage, though we see from the allusions to it in Plato’s Apology that it was already famous as literature at the end of Socrates’ life. But the reason for its original ill-success is fairly indicated by Aristophanes himself in our extant version of the play; it contains neither horse-play nor bawdry.

8^ I have tried to make this clear in detail in an article in the Proceedings of the British Academy for 1917-1918, pp. 93 ff., entitled ‘Plato’s Biography of Socrates.’

9^ More than one excellent work on Plato is, for example, vitiated by the assumption that the wonderful picture of Socrates drawn in the Symposium is psychological self-revelation on the part of Plato. Whether it is really that or not, at least that is not what it professes to be.

10^ In the absence of such a volume I would refer the reader in the first instance to certain works of Professor Burnet, especially the article ‘Socrates’ in Hastings’ Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics, vol. xi; the Introduction to his edition of the Phaedo (Oxford, 1911); and Greek Philosophy, Pt. I, Thales to Plato (1914), c. 8, ‘The Life of Socrates.’ I would add a further reference to the recent excellent little Sokrates of the eminent Platonic scholar, Constantin Ritter (Tübingen, 1931). Among earlier works, Ivo Bruns, Das literarische Porträt der Griechen (1896), is particularly good.

11^ The precise date of the foundation of the Academy, the first European University, is not known, but it cannot have been before Plato’s fortieth year (388/7 B.C.), and can hardly have been much later. The Theaetetus has been fairly shown to have been written about 368 B.C., and is certainly the latest of the ‘transitional’ group, as the Republic is the earliest. (Personally I agree with those who hold that the Republic must have been substantially written either just before the foundation of the Academy or within a few years of the foundation.) The ‘late’ dialogues from Sophistes to Laws are pretty certainly all subsequent to 360 B.C.

12^ One should note in this connection the remarkable passage, Timaeus 19b ff., where Socrates is made to confess his own inability to depict the conduct of a State engaged in the activities of war or diplomacy, and appears to ascribe this deficiency to his want of political experience. There is nothing in the Republic itself like this sense of the limitations of Socrates. The reappearance of Socrates as the leading figure in the Philebus is explained by the fact that the questions dealt with there are at bottom the same as those which had been treated in earlier dialogues like the Gorgias. Of course it is not suggested that all Plato’s Socratic dialogues are close reports of actual conversations, like those recorded by Boswell, though it is likely enough that some of them are founded on actual conversations. What is meant is simply that the dialogues intend to exhibit a faithful picture of the situation, interests, and views of a real historical man.

13^ Hermodorus, who is quoted for the fact in Diogenes Laertius, iii. 6: ‘Then, at the age of twenty-eight, he [Plato] with other Socratics withdrew to Euclides at Megara.’ (The same statement is also made, ibid, ii. 106.)

14^ It is not true, as is sometimes supposed, that Aristotle ever says that the ‘Theory of Ideas’ was unknown to Socrates, though even if he had said this, it would be no more than an inference of his own. What is true is that Aristotle usually connects the theory with the names of Plato and his followers, and that in one passage (Metaphysics 1078b 11), where he speaks of ‘those who had first said that there are Forms (or Ideas),’ he may be referring to Plato (though this is not certain). Since the theory was certainly introduced into philosophical literature by the Socratic dialogues of Plato, such an expression would in any case be natural. The statement of the Nicomachean Ethics that the theory was introduced by ‘friends’ of Aristotle (Nicomachean Ethics 1096a 13) proves nothing. A doctrine of Socrates would be one held in a quarter which any disciple of Plato might speak of as ‘friendly.’

15^ It is certain, or all but certain, that all the Socratic writings of Xenophon are later than most of the ‘Socratic’ dialogues of Plato. The same thing appears to be true, so far as can be discovered, of the dialogues of Aeschines.

16^ This point is made with special effect in the posthumous volume of Burnet, Platonism (University of California Press, 1928), pp. 5 ff.

17^ Every historian who makes statements about the ‘Sophistic age’ is dependent for most of what he says on Platonic dialogues like the Protagoras and Gorgias, though a writer who regards Plato’s Socrates as a fictitious personage ought in consistency to take the same view of his Protagoras or Gorgias or Thrasymachus.

18^ Xenophon also must be depending on the testimony of older men for what we shall find to be the most illuminating things which he tells us. But in his case we have not the same reasons as we have in Plato’s for feeling confidence in the competence of his informants. The only informant whom he names, Hermogenes, the half-brother of the wealthy Callias, does not strike one in the pictures drawn of him by Plato (in the Cratylus) and Xenophon himself (in his Symposium) as a man of much discretion. It has been probably inferred that another informant was Antisthenes, who was pretty certainly an older man than either Xenophon or Plato, but there is no evidence that Xenophon had any special opportunity of communication with Antisthenes when he was engaged in the composition of his own ‘Socratic’ works, and it is hardly likely that he had. Modern speculations about possible borrowings in Xenophon from the writings of Antisthenes are, of course, only speculations.

Top ↑


Chapter II. The Early Life of Socrates

As there was no official registration of births at Athens, we have no direct record of the birth of Socrates, son of Sophroniscus and Phaenarete, of the Antiochid tribe, and the deme, or, as we should say, parish, or ward, of Alopece. Indirectly, however, we can fix the year of his birth within very narrow limits. There was, of course, an official record of his trial and condemnation, which fell in the spring of the year 399 B.C. (the ‘year of Laches’), and Plato has told us that at the time of the trial he was seventy, or rather older.1 Hence we shall be very nearly right if we assume him to have been born in the year 470, only nine years after the decisive repulse of the Persian army at Plataea. Thus, when Socrates was born, Pericles was still a very young man, Sophocles and Euripides were lads; Aeschylus had produced his great drama of patriotism, the Persians, some two years before, at the charges of Pericles. The philosopher might have been present as a boy at the performance of the Agamemnon, and have witnessed every one of the great tragedies of Sophocles and Euripides. All the noble buildings and works of art with which Athens was enriched in the Periclean age, the Long Walls which connected the city with the port of Piraeus, the Parthenon, the statues of Phidias, the frescoes of Polygnotus, were begun and completed under his eyes. The confederacy of Delos, the germ of the Athenian maritime empire, had been formed less than ten years before his birth; he must already have been old enough to be beginning to take notice of what was happening around him when the foundations of Periclean democracy were laid by the ostracism of Pericles’ rival Cimon, son of Miltiades (461 B.C.), and the institution of public pay for the democratic jury-courts. He was already a young man of twenty-four or twenty-five when Athens and Sparta concluded the ‘thirty years’ peace,’ which left Athens, at the price of abandoning her aspirations to dominion on land, free to consolidate her control over the Aegean and to become the first naval power in the world. He was already on the verge of forty at the outbreak of the long war which was to end in the destruction of Athenian greatness. It is important to remember these facts for a very simple reason. The picture of Socrates which has inevitably dominated the imagination of all later ages is that drawn by Plato in the dialogues which deal with his trial and death as an old man, just as the picture which we all have in our minds when we think of Johnson is that of Boswell, who never saw him until he was close on fifty-four and had all the struggles of a lifetime behind him. We cannot even begin to understand Socrates historically until we are clear on the point that his youth and early manhood were spent in a society sundered from that in which Plato and Xenophon grew up by the same sort of gulf which divides ‘post-war’ from ‘pre-war’ Europe.

We do not know much about the parents of Socrates. Plato tells us in the Laches (180d) that Sophroniscus was connected by ties of close friendship with the family of his famous fellow-demesman the ‘just’ Aristides, and implies that he was a man of some consideration in the deme. In the Crito (50d) it is implied that he was conscientiously careful to give his son the recognized elementary education in ‘gymnastic’ and music. Phaenarete — the name seems to indicate that she was a woman of good family — had, by another husband, a son named Patrocles (Plato, Euthydemus, 297e); Plato tells us in the Theaetetus (149a) that she had high skill as an accoucheuse. (The statement has sometimes been regarded as a pleasantry, but there seems to be no point in it if it is an invention, and we are not, of course, to commit the anachronism of supposing that Phaenarete was a professional midwife.)2 The Alexandrian tradition, still commonly repeated as fact, is that Sophroniscus was a craftsman, a statuary, or stone-cutter, and we know from both Pausanias (I. xxii. 8) and Diogenes Laertius (ii. 19) that in the second century A.D. a group of the Graces on the Acropolis was shown as the work of Socrates himself. This, however, seems very doubtful. Archaeologists seem to be agreed that the group described by Pausanias must belong to a sculptor of an earlier period; (the name Socrates was a common one). The earliest extant reference to Socrates as the son of a worker in stone is found in some satiric lines quoted from the third-century verse-writer Timon of Phlius, and, as Burnet has said, it seems at least plain that neither Plato nor Xenophon had ever heard anything of the story. If Plato had known it, he would hardly have made Socrates say, as he does in the Apology, that when he set himself to look round for a wiser man than himself he began at once with the politicians, turned next to the poets, and only explored the ‘artisans’ last. I think with Burnet that the statement probably arose from a misunderstanding of a playful reference by Socrates in Plato3 to Daedalus, the legendary maker of wooden images, as his ancestor, and that the true meaning of this jest is that the family had a pedigree which traced their line back to Daedalus, exactly as the house of the Philaidae, to which Pisistratus and Alcibiades belonged, traced their origin to Aeacus. In any case, it seems plain that if Plato is to be trusted, Socrates himself had never followed any craft. He is depicted as always having had absolute leisure to occupy himself as his tastes directed, and as having consorted from the first with the most distinguished men of Athens, the circles of Pericles and Cimon.

Whether Sophroniscus was a statuary or not, we must not make the mistake of thinking of Socrates as belonging to a needy class, like the modern ‘proletariat.’ He was extremely poor in his old age — after a disastrous war which resulted in a general ‘financial crisis’ — but Plato makes a point of it that this poverty was directly due to absorption in a ‘mission’ which left no time for attendance to ‘personal affairs’ (Apology, 23c). Down to his forty-sixth year, at any rate, he cannot have belonged to the poorest class of Athenian citizens, as he was still serving in 424 as a ‘hoplite’ or fully-armed infantryman, and must have been officially credited with the income which rendered him liable to this service. The prominence given to his alleged neediness in the burlesques produced the year after by the comic poets suggests, though it does not absolutely prove, that his impoverishment was then recent. Hence there seems some reason to believe a statement of the third-century scholar Demetrius of Phalerum (Plutarch, Aristides, I) that Socrates inherited, besides a dwelling-house, a modest capital (seventy minae), which was invested for him by his friend Crito.

From his earliest days Socrates must have been something of what we call an ‘oddity,’ both physically and mentally. His physical robustness and powers of endurance are dwelt upon by both Plato and Xenophon, and partly explain the excellence of his record as a fighting-man. It is further testimony to his physical vigour that when he died at the age of seventy he left two small children, one of whom appears to have been an infant in arms.4 Stress is laid upon his exceptional continence and abstemiousness in eating and drinking, and also upon his power, on appropriate occasions, of drinking deep without being affected by the winecup. In his manhood he used to wear the same single garment winter and summer, and habitually went barefoot, even, according to Plato, in the rigours of a winter campaign.5 But he was very far from being handsome or well-made. Aristophanes compared his walk to the strut of a waterfowl, and made fun of his habit of rolling his eyes; Plato and Xenophon both allude to the breadth of his nostrils and the marked snubness of his nose, as well as to some peculiarity of his eyes, which may be either their prominence or the breadth of the space between them. (Compare the accounts of Plato, Symposium, 215b ff., and Xenophon, Symposium, 5.) He looked, says Alcibiades in Plato’s Symposium, like some grotesque, a satyr or a Silenus.

Mentally, also, Socrates was in more than one way singular. His most striking singularity was the mysterious ‘voice’ or ‘supernatural sign,’6 which attended him from the days of his childhood. According to Plato, who treats the peculiarity very lightly, the ‘sign’ manifested itself sporadically, often on very trivial occasions, and always took the form of a sudden inhibition;7 experience showed that neglect of its warnings commonly led to unpleasant consequences. Xenophon, who had a vein of superstition in his own character, makes rather more of this oddity, which he treats as a kind of private oracle, and insists that it also gave positive directions, which it was not safe to neglect, for the actions of both Socrates and his friends. The fourth-century dialogue Theages, wrongly attributed to Plato, contains a number of striking anecdotes about persons who had disregarded warnings given by the ‘sign,’ always with disastrous consequences. Plato’s version of the thing, as the least sensational, is likely to be the most accurate. It is clear from all the accounts that the ‘sign’ was nothing of the nature of ‘conscience.’ It had nothing to do with right and wrong, and is never appealed to, in any of the accounts of it, on points of moral conduct, but amounts to a sort of ‘uncanny’ flair for bad luck. Its chief interest for us is that it is one indication among others that Socrates really possessed the temperament of the ‘visionary,’ though, unlike most seers of visions, he kept that side of his nature well in check, as St. Paul did his gift for ‘speaking with tongues.’ Another mark of the visionary temperament dwelt on by Plato is his liability to sudden fits of absorption and abstraction, amounting at times to actual trance or ‘ecstasy.’ These were apparently usually of brief duration, but Plato records one which befell the philosopher as he was serving before Potidaea, and lasted the whole of a day and a night.8 Facts of this kind throw a light on the strong vein of mysticism which is characteristic of Plato’s Socratic dialogues. This is commonly interpreted as evidence for the presence of a mystical tendency in Plato himself, but in view of the marked elimination of this strain from the later dialogues in which Socrates has ceased to be prominent, it seems more reasonable to infer that the mysticism of such works as the Symposium and Phaedrus belongs in the first instance to Socrates — a point to which we shall have to recur later on.

What curbed this vein and prevented it from developing, in the case of Socrates, into superstition was, according to Plato, not only the ‘obstinate rationality’ which he shared with Samuel Johnson, but the shrewd humour in which he also resembled the ‘sage’ of Fleet Street. It is this humour which his opponents in Plato’s dialogues speak of as his ‘habitual irony.’ Irony, in this, the primitive sense of the word, means the disagreeable characteristic of the man who contrives to evade his responsibilities by an affected disparagement of his abilities.9 Socrates is accused by his unfavourable critics in Plato of this affectation because he habitually represents himself as the humble inquirer who wants to sit at the feet of those who know more than himself, while it is manifest that he is really their intellectual superior. Hence his disclaimers are taken as uncandid excuses for confining himself to the easy task of exposing the deficiencies of other men. Plato’s own conviction, of course, is that Socrates’ professions are perfectly serious. He declares himself ignorant for the same reason that he thinks very little of the wisdom upon which some of his contemporaries plume themselves: he has a sound and exacting standard of what real knowledge should be, and therefore knows how far short he and all the rest of them come of reaching that standard. Hence he alone sees both himself and the rest of mankind in their true proportions, and the contrast between men’s pretensions and their performance appeals to his sense of humour.

The almost universal adoption of symbolic language borrowed from sexual passion by the mystics of all times and places seems to point to a real connection between the mystical and the erotic temperament. Socrates was clearly no exception to this rule, and it is a consequence of the manners of the fashionable circles of his age that his imagery is borrowed from the vocabulary of romantic attachment between persons of the same sex. The most striking example is afforded by what is said in Plato about the famous association between him and his brilliant fellow-citizen Alcibiades, a man somewhere between fifteen and twenty years younger than himself.10 This attachment, which must date from a time when Alcibiades was a mere boy and Socrates a man in his thirties, is described by Plato in the language of romantic passion, and Plato is confirmed on the point by a still surviving sentence put into the mouth of Socrates by Aeschines in his dialogue Alcibiades.11 Xenophon is naturally silent about the attachment of Socrates to Alcibiades, which, as we shall see, was one of the principal counts against him in the mind of the democratic politicians who brought him to trial, but he agrees with Plato’s representation that it was Socrates’ habit to speak of himself playfully as a lifelong victim of Eros and a master in the ars amoris.12 Both Plato and Xenophon make it perfectly clear that this language was playful, and we must be careful not to misunderstand it. The absolute moral purity of Socrates is the presupposition of the story of his ‘temptation’ put into the mouth of Alcibiades himself in the Symposium, and the whole object of the treatment of the subject in Plato’s two great ‘erotic’ dialogues, Symposium and Phaedrus, is to disentangle the amor mysticus from sensual or sentimental corruptions.13

We have to think of Socrates in his early manhood, then, as an original genius in whose character there was a unique blend of the passionate lover, the religious mystic, the eager rationalist, and the humorist; we are to reconstruct, as far as we can on the strength of the surviving records, the reaction upon such a character of the intense intellectual life of the Periclean age. The task is a hazardous one, but I believe it can be accomplished if we trust to indications given us by Plato, and interpret our other evidence in the light of them.

In one respect, indeed, we have probably to reckon with an influence from a still earlier generation. The Socrates of the Platonic dialogues frequently refers to the dogmas of the Orphic religion as supporting his own convictions about the immortality of the soul and the importance of the life to come, and the details of the imaginative myths which he relates about Heaven and Hell in the Gorgias, Phaedo, Republic, are notoriously Orphic. Plato, too, as we see from allusions in the Laws, regarded ‘ancient sayings,’ which plainly mean the Orphic doctrines, as fables with a kernel of imperishable religious truth; but we see also from the unsparing attack on immoral mythology and religion in the second book of the Republic, which is aimed much more at Orpheus than at Homer, that it was Plato’s view that by the time of his own birth14 Orphicism had degenerated into vulgar trafficking in ‘pardons’ and ‘indulgences.’ Contemporary Orphicism is not likely, therefore, to have inspired either Plato or Socrates with respect. Pindar’s greatest Orphic odes, however, belong to the years just before Socrates’ birth, and this suggests the probability that Socrates really had been initiated in the Orphic religion in childhood15 and permanently impressed by it. That fact, if it is a fact, will contribute to account for the standing connection which we shall find between Socrates and the Pythagoreans of Thebes and Phlius, as well as for Plato’s obvious anxiety in the dialogue Euthyphro to exhibit the difference between the piety of Socrates and that of the fantastic sectary Euthyphron, and for the existence of a dialogue Telauges by Aeschines, in which Socrates was brought into company with an ‘other-worldly’ devotee of particularly dirty habits, and apparently made to criticize his ways.

It was, no doubt, from the spirit of Periclean Athens that Socrates derived the lifelong sense of the importance of implicit obedience to lawful authority and the reverence for strict constitutionality which led him in later life to oppose violation of the constitution, alike by the angry democracy and by its subverters, at grave personal risk, and, in the end, to submit to a trial which it was intended by his accusers he should evade, and a sentence from which he might easily have escaped, in vindication of the right of the State to pronounce on the conduct of its citizens. His whole life was a signal example of that reverence for law which we are accustomed to think Roman rather than Greek, and yet singularly free from the besetting Roman vice of exalting the mere letter of the law above its spirit.

More needs to be said about the intellectual atmosphere of the society in which Socrates passed his youth and earlier manhood, and its influence upon him. The important fact we have to keep before our minds is that the rise of Athens to political and commercial importance in the time of Cimon and Pericles had made it, like London in our own days, a great capital and a place of resort for the thinkers of the Hellenic world. It had become a kind of ‘clearing-house’ for ideas of all kinds. This is why, in the next century, Plato could establish at Athens an Academy which became an ‘international’ centre of higher education, and why when we hear of the science and philosophy of the ancient Greeks we think at once of the ‘schools of Athens,’ though, in fact, philosophy and science originated outside Athens and were so uncongenial to the Athenian character that Socrates and Plato themselves are the only Athenian philosophers of any note.

Philosophy and science, as yet undiscriminated from one another, had been the creation of the intellectual curiosity of the Greeks of the Great Ionian cities of the seaboard of Asia Minor, who set themselves, from somewhere about 600 B.C. onwards, to construct a rational and coherent theory of the world around them. Within a couple of generations of the origination of the intellectual movement, the impulse had been carried to the Greek Societies of Southern Italy by one of the greatest of the Ionian men of genius, Pythagoras, the real founder of mathematics, with the result that the West became rapidly still more important than the East for the future development of European thought. The primary interest of the original Ionian men of science had been in the ‘things above us,’ the heavenly bodies which seem to move in a way which is at once complex and baffling and yet regulated by some uniform law, if only we could discover what that law is. The rise of Greek medicine had then led to a displacement of astronomical by biological speculation as the dominating influence in the ‘scientific world,’ while mathematics had attained a high degree of development and had suggested to the Pythagoreans the thought that the science of number itself is probably the key to the secrets of the universe.16 By the time that Socrates was entering on his twenties the Eastern and Western theories of the universe were crystallizing into a certain opposition to one another, of which the most prominent ‘outward and visible sign’ was the different account of the earth’s shape and place in the scheme of things given in the two systems. The general Eastern view was that there is a single stuff of which everything, including our own minds, is made. This stuff is ‘air,’ and by air was meant mist or vapour. Everything is mist or vapour, and the differences between things are due simply to variations in the degree of condensation or rarefaction of this primitive stuff. Even the human ‘soul’ is air, being, in fact, just the portion of the surrounding atmosphere which we draw into our bodies by respiration. This is why we only have life and consciousness so long as we continue to breathe, and why we ‘give up the ghost’ when we die. The earth, a large mass of highly-condensed air which lies in the centre of our particular ‘world,’ or stellar system, is a broad disc which floats on the air beneath it as a leaf floats on the surface of a stream. As this Eastern view was in principle monistic, the rival Western views were in principle dualistic or pluralistic. The best known of these theories to the average modern reader is that of Empedocles, the founder of the Sicilian medical school, who held that so far from being air in varying states of condensation, all things are compounds of four primitive ‘roots’ (the elements of a later terminology), fire, atmospheric air, water, ‘earth.’ A still more striking contrast with the Eastern theory is afforded by the view of the Pythagoreans, who tried to conceive of things in a strictly mathematical way as so many figures constituted by ‘units’ or ‘points,’ arranged in characteristic geometrical patterns in a circumambient ‘space,’ which was not clearly discriminated from mist or darkness. Now the Pythagoreans had discovered the spherical shape of the earth, and the consequent impossibility of supposing it to float upon any support. They went back to the brilliant idea of Anaximander, who, though he supposed the earth to be drum-shaped, had declared in the earliest days of Ionian science that it is not supported by anything, but swings free in the centre of the whole stellar system because it is symmetrically placed, and there is thus no reason why it should deviate in one direction rather than in another. This direct clash between the typically Eastern and Western views of the shape of the earth is a good example of the condition of scientific thought in the middle of the fifth century. Science had been zealously pursued for a century and a half, with the result, as Socrates is made to hint in Plato’s Phaedo, that nothing seemed certain but that if any of its rival exponents were right, all the others must be wrong (96a-b, 99b-c).

Even more disconcerting than the contradictory assertions of the conflicting scientific schools was the radical criticism upon all of them of the Zeno. Starting from the rationalist principle that what cannot be thought without self-contradiction cannot be true, Parmenides had declared that motion and change, the fundamental characteristics of the world as described by science, are self-contradictory, and must therefore be illusory. What really is must be a single, uniform, unchanging ‘Absolute’;17 since Nature, as envisaged by the cosmologists, is not such an Absolute but a scene of incessant motion and transformation, Nature can only be an illusion. Zeno had carried the war into the heart of the enemy’s camp by subjecting the mathematical principles of the Pythagoreans to a searching examination which appeared to prove that mathematical thought itself is a mass of contradictions, and, in fact, led to a reconstruction of mathematical fundamental concepts which began in the age of Plato and has barely been completed in our own.18a The effect of this apparently unanswerable assault on the first elements of rational knowledge was to produce by the middle of the fifth century B.C. a wide-spread general scepticism of the very possibility of knowledge of the natural world. By the time that Socrates was a young man of twenty the ablest and most outstanding men were all turning away from the physical world as an object of study; it was almost exclusively the second-rate minds which went on patching up the old systems. The first-rate men, like Protagoras of Abdera, were turning their thoughts in a different direction. In an age of rapid moral and political progress the need was felt for thought-out and clearly formulated principles in legislation, politics, the personal conduct of life, to take the place of reliance on tradition and custom, and here there seemed to be a fruitful opening for employment of intelligence to real purpose. This explains the rise of a new profession, that of the ‘sophist,’19 or paid ‘educator of men.’ Men who a little while earlier would have been students of Nature found a new and remunerative occupation in travelling from one city to another as professed exponents of ‘virtue’ or ‘goodness,’ that is, of the knowledge ‘how to conduct one’s private affairs and the affairs of one’s city well,’ the precise knowledge a youthful aspirant to power and distinction would be most anxious to acquire. The humanistic studies of Europe have their beginning in this movement, as the natural sciences have theirs in the cosmological speculations of the ‘wise men’ of Miletus. The rapid rise of an imperial democracy in Attica in the Periclean age naturally made of Athens a world-capital in which the professor of ‘goodness’ could make sure of an eager audience and a rich harvest.

Both the older interest in mathematical and physical science and the new interest in the humanistic study of law and morals were fully represented in the Athens of Pericles. The old science, in its Eastern version, with its flat earth, had indeed been brought to Athens in that statesman’s early childhood by Anaxagoras, and the tradition accepted by both Plato and Isocrates represents Anaxagoras as having been charged with the education of Pericles himself.20 Anaxagoras had probably been compelled by the political opponents of Pericles to leave Athens to escape a sentence for ‘impiety’ before Socrates was of full age,21 but throughout the succeeding years cosmologies of the Eastern type were still being taught there by his successor, Archelaus, and by Diogenes of Apollonia. The great geometer Hippocrates of Chios had established himself in the city. Plato assures us, and there is no reason to doubt the fact, that Parmenides and Zeno had visited the city, where Socrates made their acquaintance, while he was still a very young man, and Zeno must have lived there for some time, as more than one eminent Athenian paid him handsome fees for his instruction.22 Plato’s dialogues depict for us the sensation aroused by the visits of the outstanding leaders of the ‘humanistic’ movement, a Protagoras and a Gorgias. Protagoras, at any rate, must have had the entrée to the circle of Pericles himself, who included him in the Commission appointed to make a constitution for his important colony of Thurii (443 B.C.) in South Italy, and Zeno seems also to have been among his associates.

It seems quite certain that Socrates in early life acquired a full knowledge of the science of the age and a full mastery of its humanistic culture. This is Plato’s standing representation, and the best evidence of its truth is that it is borne out by the really remarkable admissions of Xenophon. For his apologetic purpose he is anxious to prove that Socrates took his own utilitarian view of the sciences, that he thought one should know enough of geometry to ‘take the measure of a piece of land one is receiving or conveying,’ but should not trouble one’s head about ‘the intricate diagrams,’ and enough of astronomy to be able to ‘tell the time of night or month or year for the purposes of a journey or voyage or night watch,’ without concerning one’s mind with ‘planets and wandering stars, and their distances from the earth, and their orbits and causes.’ Yet in both cases Xenophon (Memorabilia IV. vii. 1-6) at once adds, ‘yet he was not unfamiliar with the subject, ‘yet he was not uninstructed in these matters’ (thus his alleged attitude was not the contempt of ignorance).23

Plato tells us more on the point in the autobiographical narrative which the Phaedo puts into the mouth of Socrates.24 Socrates began, we are told, as an enthusiast for ‘research into Nature,’ eager to discover the ‘causes of the coming of things into being and their passing away.’ He studied the various current cosmological theories, Eastern and Western — it is indicated that he began with those of the two contemporary teachers of the Eastern type of theory at Athens, Atchelaus and Diogenes of Apollonia — and was particularly struck by the disagreement about the shape of the earth. He knew the biological doctrines of the Sicilian Empedocles and the theories of the Italian Alcmaeon of Crotona about the brain as an organ of mental life, and had been much troubled by mathematical difficulties connected with the notion of the unit, a problem raised by Zeno. At first the flat contradictions between the tenets of rival theorists brought him to desperation, but a passage read to him from the book of Anaxagoras came as a revelation. Mind, said Anaxagoras, is the cause of all natural law and order, just as mind is the cause of the orderliness and coherence of human action. To Socrates this suggested that the universe at large is the embodiment, like a properly conducted human life, of coherent rational plan. If Mind is the cause of the world’s structure, the earth and everything else in the universe must have just the shape, position, place in the scheme, which it is best that each of them should have. He set himself to the study of Anaxagoras in the hope that he had found a teacher who would put an end to scientific uncertainty by showing how it is best that every detail of the universe should be disposed, and how it must therefore be disposed in a world controlled by Mind. These hopes were speedily dashed when it appeared that Anaxagoras merely introduced Mind into his scheme to provide the initial impetus to the vortex-motion by which he supposed stellar systems to be generated, without making any use of the thought that a universe controlled by Mind must be the embodiment of intelligent plan. It was this early disappointment which led Socrates, as he humorously puts it, to conclude that he ‘had no head for the natural sciences,’ and to strike out a line of investigation and a method of his own.

The nature of this new method we shall have to consider later, when we are discussing the philosophy of Socrates. For the present, it is important to observe that the situation presupposed in the story told by Plato is historically exactly that which existed at Athens in the youth of Socrates, and that Plato is careful to direct attention to the fact by the copious details given of the conflicting doctrines between which Socrates hesitates. Plato is clearly not describing his own early history, since the intellectual situation had been entirely changed by his own time, and the theories he describes had become obsolete.25 And we cannot well suppose that he means to describe the ‘growth of a philosopher’s mind’ in general (it is no essential of the process to be perplexed by the question of the shape of the earth). He clearly means to relate what he believes to be the facts about an intellectual crisis in the life of his hero Socrates; he had, as we have seen, ample opportunity for learning the relevant facts from Socrates himself and others, and we may therefore be reasonably satisfied that his narrative is substantially accurate. Of course, since he gives us no chronological indications except that the events belong to the early life of Socrates, it is quite possible that the intellectual revolution he describes in a page or two may have taken some considerable time for its completion.

Plato’s statements ought pretty certainly to be taken in connection with the definite assertion made by Theophrastus (Physics, Opinions of the Natural Philosophers fr. 4.), the associate and successor of Aristotle, and the earliest writer on the history of Greek philosophy, that Socrates was actually a member of the school of Archelaus, the Athenian who succeeded Anaxagoras when that philosopher had to leave Athens. The statement passed from Theophrastus to the whole series of Alexandrian writers on the history of philosophy who took his work as their fountainhead, and can hardly be anything but true. Theophrastus himself was at least certainly in Athens in the lifetime of Plato, and may have been, as some accounts make him, an actual member of the Academy, and was a careful writer on such points of history. Moreover, his statement is confirmed by another associate of Aristode, Aristoxenus of Tarentum, the writer on musical theory. Aristoxenus asserted (Fr. 25, Fragmenta Historicum Graeca, ii. 280) that the connection between Archelaus and Socrates began when the latter was a lad of seventeen, and continued for many years. He connected the statement with a good deal of scandal-mongering, the object of which is to discredit the memory of Socrates, but the worthlessness of his scandal is no reason for disbelieving his assertion about the fact of the association. Moreover, we also know that the fifth-century tragic poet Ion of Chios recorded the fact that Archelaus and Socrates visited the island of Samos together when Socrates was a young man (Diogenes Laertius, ii. 23). Since Ion also recorded in his Memoirs his own meeting with Pericles and the tragic poet Sophocles in Chios in the year 441/40, it is a probable conjecture that the story about Archelaus and Socrates belongs to the same context, and that Ion met them together at the time of his meeting with Pericles. This was during the revolt of Samos from the Athenians, and the Athenian blockade of the island. Archelaus and Socrates (then a man of twenty-eight or twenty-nine) must be presumed to have been serving in the Athenian blockading force, and the reason why Plato makes no reference to the incident when he has occasion to mention the campaigns of Socrates will be simply that it was long before his own time.26 Plato tells us nothing of this connection of Socrates with Archelaus, but it manifestly provides just the right framework for his story of the introduction of Socrates to the book of Archelaus’ old teacher.27

Apart from Plato’s accounts of the meeting of Socrates with Parmenides and Zeno, and his disappointment with the book of Anaxagoras, and the just-quoted statements about his connection with the school of Archelaus, we have no direct information about the events of his life down to the outbreak of the Archidamian War in the year 431. We may, however, draw certain inferences with fair confidence. It is natural to think of him as for some time, at any rate, continuing his connection with Archelaus and his associates; we need not suppose that his engrossment in his new method of inquiry was completed in a few weeks or months. Perhaps we may even conjecture that when Archelaus retired — we do not know when this was — Socrates was to all intents and purposes his successor. This may sound startling to us when we remember the vigour with which the Socrates of Plato’s Apology denies that he has any ‘disciples,’ or has ever professed to be any man’s ‘teacher,’ but it is strictly consistent with the denials of Plato. What Socrates is concerned to deny in the Apology is that he has ever followed the profession of a paid ‘educator of men,’ or taken ‘pupils.’28 This is quite compatible with his having at some time before Plato’s own birth been the unpaid head of a body of ‘associates’ over whose studies he had presided. (The regular word for the relation of such a student to the director of the group, we must remember, was not mathetes, pupil, but hetairos, associate; the difference lies in the implication of professionalism which is present in the former word, but absent from the latter.) And there is in fact a good deal of evidence which implies that Socrates really had, in his earlier days, been something very much like the head of an organized ‘school.’

This is clearly the presupposition of the caricature of Aristophanes in the Clouds. Socrates is burlesqued there as the head of a body of students — the burlesque naturally calls them ‘pupils’ — who live together in his house, and it is taken for granted that they are supplied with such requisites of a scientific school as maps and apparatus. These inmates of the ‘notion-factory,’ as Aristophanes calls the house of Socrates, are depicted as combining two characters. They are a set of ragged and hungry ascetics with unusual ‘spiritualistic’ views. This explains why a laugh is raised against them by calling them ‘wisest spirits’ (Clouds 94), a phrase which in the Attic of the fifth century suggests ghosts. They are also devotees of astronomy, geography, and geology (Clouds 184 ff.), and profess a cosmological doctrine which we recognize at once as that of Diogenes of Apollonia, according to which everything consists of ‘air.’ This is why they are represented as praying to the Clouds, and why Socrates does his thinking swinging from a machine of some kind, to keep the air which constitutes his mind from contact with the damps of the earth’s surface (ib. 225 ff.). It is hard to see what point a burlesque of this kind could have unless there were a real basis of fact behind the distortion. Given the two facts, that Socrates held beliefs akin to those of the Orphics about the immortal soul, and that he was at one time of his life the leading spirit in a group of cosmological students with views of what we have called the Eastern type, Aristophanes’ caricature has the requisite point; unless we grant this foundation in fact, it is silly.29

There is a particularly valuable section of Xenophon’s Memoirs (I. vi.), which must refer to a time in the earlier manhood of Socrates, from which we get some light on the reality behind the Aristophanic caricature. Antiphon the Sophist, says Xenophon, was anxious to detach the ‘associates’ of Socrates, and apparently to attract them to himself. (We do not know the precise date of Antiphon, but it is certain that he is a figure of the days of the Archidamian War.) Accordingly, he openly criticized Socrates unfavourably in the hearing of these companions. He commented, in the first place, on the ascetic life of Socrates, his scanty raiment, shoeless feet, and meagre diet, all characteristics made prominent by Plato and Xenophon as well as by Aristophanes and his brother comedians. He further criticized him for his refusal to take a fee from his companions for the services done to them. Services for which no charge is made, he argued, may fairly be presumed to be worth nothing. Socrates is made to meet this second point first by drawing a comparison between the ‘wit’ who sells his knowledge and the catamite who sells his ‘charms,’ and then by explaining more precisely the nature of the relation between himself and the associates in question, with a view to showing that it is not of the kind for which payment can be decently charged. ‘A good friend,’ he says, ‘gives me the same pleasure as a good horse, or dog, or game-cock gives another man, or even more; if I know anything good, I teach it to my friends, and introduce them to others from whom I conceive they will profit in goodness. I join with my friends in unrolling the treasures of the wits of old times, which they have left behind them in written scrolls, and if we find a good thing there, we pick it out, and think we have won great gain if we become friends’ (loc. cit., 14). The Socrates depicted here is quite unlike the man with the mission to all and sundry so familiar to us from the personal recollections of Plato and Xenophon. He is quite definitely a student of ‘ancient wits,’ who must be the early philosophers and men of science. He has a circle of fellow-students round him, quite different from the leisured young men of wealthy families who clustered round him in his later years, as Plato says, for the pleasure of hearing him expose the ignorance of public men (Apology, 23c); and his relation to this circle as director of their studies is one which can plausibly be mistaken by Antiphon for that of a professional ‘master.’ Xenophon has here clearly preserved for us a valuable notice derived from some Socratic man of a time earlier than his own, and it is enough to prove that the ‘notion-factory’ of the Clouds is a distortion for comic effect of something real.

It is important to note that the fame of Socrates as a man of outstanding intellectual power must have been established in this early half of his life, and that, in particular, his relations with the famous ‘sophists’ must go back to this date. This is plainly presupposed by Plato in more than one place. The great encounter between Socrates and Protagoras, the most eminent of the sophists, depicted in Plato’s most dramatic dialogue, is manifestly imagined to take place before the outbreak of the great war had become imminent. Alcibiades, who fought in the cavalry at Potidaea (Symposium, 220d-e), is, in the Protagoras, still only on the threshold of manhood; the eminent ‘wits,’ some of them from cities which were to be ‘enemy states’ in the war, are all collected in the house of Callias on peaceful and friendly terms. Now, in the dialogue it is taken for granted that Socrates is already personally well known to all of them. He even alludes,30 as he does more than once elsewhere in Plato, to having attended one of the less expensive lectures of Prodicus. Protagoras, in particular, has made his acquaintance some years before, and pays him the compliment of saying that he had then thought him the ablest man of his years he had ever met, and has the highest confidence in his future.31 The relations of Socrates with these men, as described by Plato, though the point is sometimes overlooked, belong to the early part of his life, before he had embarked on his ‘mission,’ and they are far from unfriendly. The ‘sophists’ are never even mentioned by the Apology as one of the classes whom it became his vocation to expose. They admire his ability, though in a rather patronizing way, and his attitude to them is a characteristic mixture of respect for real attainments and polite amusement at their self-complacent unconsciousness of their limitations.

As Burnet has pointed out, we have besides more indirect evidence of the eminent position Socrates had won for himself before he was forty in intellectual circles far outside Athens. We know from Plato’s Phaedo (59b-c) the names of the persons who were present at his death-bed, and of one or two others whose presence was anticipated; and several of these names are confirmed, as those of friends of Socrates, by Xenophon. There were present, in particular, two young men from Thebes, Simmias and Cebes, once disciples of the Pythagorean Philolaus, and two Eleatics from Megara, Euclides and Terpsion. Simmias and Cebes are both named by Xenophon (Memorabilia I. ii. 48) among the men of real worth who frequented Socrates’ company with a single eye to the good of their souls. The accomplished ‘cosmopolitan’ Aristippus of Cyrene, though not actually present, was on such terms with Socrates that Plato feels that some sort of explanation has to be given of his absence, and Aristippus also is made by Xenophon, who disliked him, to figure as a member of the Socratic circle and to receive a caustic rebuke from Socrates for his indolent and voluptuous life.32 The special interest of the Pythagoreans in particular in Socrates is shown by the fact that the narrative of his death in Plato is given by Phaedo of Elis to the Pythagorean Echecrates of Phlius and a group of unnamed companions who are represented as enthusiastic admirers, eager for a full account of the great man’s last moments. Now the native cities of most of these men, Thebes, Elis, Phlius, were ‘enemy states’ during the Peloponnesian War, which went on, in spite of the ‘peace’ nominally concluded in 421 B.C., almost continually from Socrates’ fortieth year to his sixty-sixth. It seems to follow that his connection with the older men among these non-Attic philosophers must have been originated before he was forty, and that the Pythagorean groups scattered up and down the Greek world must already in those days have looked up to him as a venerated teacher. Otherwise it is hard to understand why the young disciples of the Pythagoreans from Thebes should have been eager to resort to his company as soon as the conclusion of the great war made it possible. The same sort of ‘international reputation’ is presupposed by a notice preserved to us from Aeschines that Aristippus of Cyrene in particular had first been attracted to Athens by ‘the fame of Socrates’ (Diogenes Laertius, ii. 65). It is plainly implied in all these facts that Socrates, contrary to some modern representations, was from an early time in his life generally well known as an outstanding figure in intellectual circles far outside Athens. This is strictly in accord with Plato’s account of the impression he made as a young man upon such eminent ‘foreigners’ as Parmenides and Protagoras, but quite inconsistent with the quaint nineteenth-century theory which makes him into an eccentric ‘proletarian’ of genius.

The same view of his position in early life is presupposed in the famous story, told at length by Plato in the Apology, of the declaration of the Delphic oracle that ‘no man living was wiser than Socrates’ (Apology, 21a ff.). In spite of the scepticism of a few modern German writers, there can be no) reasonable doubt that the delivery of the oracle is an historical fact. Plato could not have represented Socrates as telling the story at length before his judges, many of whom must have read the Apology, unless he had really talked about it; and it would have been insane to tell such a story, and to offer to produce witnesses to its truth, as Socrates does, unless the thing had really happened. Nor is there any difficulty in understanding why the Delphic priestess delivered the oracle, though some historians have puzzled themselves about the matter. As Socrates tells us in Plato, the oracle was given to his friend Chaerephon, who had put the leading question, ‘Is there any one alive wiser than Socrates?’ Of course, as happens in such cases, Chaerephon was given the answer he had directly invited. The really instructive point is that the question should have been asked, for the putting of it means that Socrates must already have enjoyed such a reputation that an admirer could ask it without making himself ridiculous ; it could only be asked about a man who was already famous in the circle round him as a ‘wit.’ Now, Plato makes it quite clear that, in his own belief, Chaerephon’s question was put to the oracle before the outbreak of the Peloponnesian War, that is, before Socrates was forty. For Socrates is made in the Apology to account for his popularity with the young men of his later years as a consequence of the enjoyment they derived from his exercise of his mission to expose the ignorance of their elders, and to account for this mission as a duty laid upon him by the delivery of the oracle. Now this wide popularity with young men and growing lads is presupposed in Plato’s dialogue Charmides, where Socrates, who has just returned from his campaign before Potidaea (431-430) at the opening of the war, is made at once to inquire after ‘the present condition of philosophy’ at Athens, and the signs of interest in it on the part of ‘the young’ (Charmides, 153d). The delivery of the oracle, then, according to Plato, presumably belongs to a still earlier date.

It is important to dwell on this incident of the oracle, since, if Plato’s representation can be trusted, it seems to have brought on a spiritual crisis in the life of Socrates. From the notices Plato has given us of his earlier life, we should naturally think of him chiefly as a prominent man in specially intellectual circles, at home in the advanced science of his age, though profoundly dissatisfied with the actual state of knowledge, and holding definitely original views of his own about the presuppositions and methods of philosophical inquiry. But as yet, though he is respected by all the intellectuals of his age, and has a group of devoted associates who look up to him as the foremost of all the ‘wits,’ there is nothing about him of the man with a mission to all and sundry to convince them of their ignorance of all that it most becomes a man to know, and of the supreme importance of ‘tending their own souls.’ That, according to Plato, was apparently just what distinguished the Socrates of later life from the Socrates of whom the pedant in Aristophanes’ play is an intelligible caricature.

According to the version of the matter given in the Apology, the mission was the direct outcome of the oracle given by Apollo. Socrates explains that he was at first astounded by the god’s opinion of him, since he was well aware that he possessed no particular wisdom. He therefore set to work to prove Apollo to be a liar by finding some one wiser than himself. He looked for such a man in the first instance among the prominent public men of the city, the ‘politicians,’ then among the poets, finally among the tradesmen and artisans, but in all cases to no purpose. In the first two classes he found no real knowledge at all; neither politicians nor poets could give any intelligible account of the principles of their statesmanship or their art. The artisans had the advantage of the others in so far as they really understood their own trades, but, unfortunately, they fancied themselves to understand other and more important things equally well. In time, the true meaning of the oracle dawned on Socrates. The meaning was that mankind are universally ignorant of the one thing it is most imperative to know, how to conduct their lives aright, how to ‘tend’ their own souls, and ‘make them as good as possible,’ and they are universally blind to this ignorance. Socrates is the one exception; if he, too, does not possess this supremely important knowledge, he knows its importance, and he knows his own ignorance of it; he is, at least, the ‘one-eyed’ in a kingdom of the ‘blind,’ and the wisest of men, as men go. This is why he feels it a duty laid on him by God to persist in seeking the supreme knowledge, and to try to induce any man, fellow-citizen or stranger, who will listen to him to seek it with him. This, according to the Apology, is the way in which the ‘wit’ Socrates became the ‘founder of moral philosophy.’

It is, of course, plain on the face of it that there is an element of humour in the way in which the story of the oracle is used in this narrative, but, to have any point at all, it must be intended to be a record of historical fact in its main presupposition, that Socrates, in middle life, went through a period of crisis as a result of which he emerged a man with a clear consciousness of a ‘mission,’ and that the response of the oracle played a part in inducing the crisis. It may not be insignificant that Plato represents him as making the attempt to ‘convert’ a young man of promise, Plato’s own uncle Charmides, just after the campaign of Potidaea, during which he had experienced the twenty-four hours’ ‘rapt’ or ‘trance’ described in the Symposium. If we knew more of the facts we might find that his ‘call’ to be a prophet came to him during that vision, and Burnet may well have been happily inspired in suggesting that this explains why in Plato we find him so often using the language of military duty to describe his sense of the vocation thus laid upon him by God. At least it seems clear that by Plato’s account the conviction of being a man set apart for a special duty to mankind dated with him from about the beginning of the Peloponnesian War, and not earlier. If we think of him as being what he must have been before Chaerephon had put his momentous question to Apollo, the picture drawn by Plato in the opening pages of the Parmenides, the account of his early days in the Phaedo, the recollections of the unknown source from whom Xenophon derived what he tells us about the relations between Socrates and Antiphon, and the amusing burlesque of the Clouds, will be found to harmonize with one another admirably.33

We can gather something from Plato and others of the persons who must have formed the ‘circle’ of Socrates in these days before the great war. In the first place, among his own most immediate friends, there would be his wealthy and devoted friend and fellow-demesman Crito, a man of about his own age. There was also the excitable admirer Chaerephon, laughed at by the comic poets for his sallow skin, dusky complexion, and half-starved appearance, and represented by Aristophanes as the confederate who plays the ‘spirits’ in Socrates’ séances.34 Some of the older men who figure later on as ‘Socratics’ may probably be regarded as associates dating from this general period, such as, in all probability, Aristippus of Cyrene and the contentious, bitter-tongued, and ascetic Antisthenes; perhaps, too, as we have said, Euclides and Terpsion, die Eleatics of Megara. Plato, Xenophon, and Aeschines were, of course, not yet born. Among the eminent men who must have stood in relations of close personal intimacy with the philosopher from the very outbreak of the great war, we have to remark first and foremost the most brilliant of all, Alcibiades, the evil genius of the Athenian democracy, which alternately spoiled him and turned on him, and next, two kinsmen of Plato’s own, his uncle Charmides and his mother’s cousin Critias, both destined to disgrace themselves even more deeply than Alcibiades.35 We may add to the list, on the evidence of the Republic, Plato’s own elder brothers, Adimantus and Glaucon, and the family of the wealthy Syracusan manufacturer Cephalus, a protégé of Pericles, and father of the famous speech-writer Lysias. Plato and Aeschines further represent the philosopher as on familiar terms with members of the more immediate circle of Pericles, especially his morganatic wife, the famous Aspasia,36 and the enormously rich Callias son of Hipponicus, the wealthiest Athenian of the day. Since Aeschines introduced into a lost Socratic dialogue, Miltiades, Miltiades son of Stesagoras, a member of the great house of the Philaidae, it would appear that Socrates had the entrée to the circle of Cimon as well as to that of Pericles. We further learn from Plato’s Laches that he had an old-established friendship with the families of Thucydides son of Melesias and the great Aristides; also that he was well known to the wealthy, respectable, and unfortunate Nicias, the leader of the more moderate and responsible section of the Athenian democracy in the years after the death of Pericles, and the opponent of the more militant party who made their idols successively of Cleon and Alcibiades. Plato several times alludes to an early friendship with another prominent man of a still more remote time, Damon of Oea, an eminent musician who was believed, like Anaxagoras, to have ‘educated’ Pericles, and to have prompted some of his democratic measures.

The writers of the Alexandrian age also relate anecdotes about a personal friendship between Socrates and the tragic poet Euripides, a man probably some twelve years his senior, and quote in confirmation passages from contemporary comedies in which Euripides was twitted with deriving the inspiration of his plays from Socrates.37 In the absence of any earlier and more precise information we cannot, of course, say whether there was any foundation for these jests beyond the spirit of inquiry and distrust of conventional opinion which is common to the tragedian and the philosopher. A famous younger tragic poet, Agathon, does appear in Plato as a friend and admirer of Socrates; the Symposium professes to describe a party held in his house to celebrate his tragic victory of the year 415 B.C. Aristophanes is one of the guests at the party, and Plato’s assumption is that, in spite of his burlesque of eight years before, he and Socrates are on terms of perfect good-fellowship. Since, as we see from the Apology,38 reminiscences of the Clouds were held by Plato to have helped to secure the condemnation of Socrates by creating a prejudice in the minds of the judges, I cannot think it likely that Plato should have imagined such a relation for himself after the death of his Master. We should rather accept his representation as historical fact, and draw the obvious conclusion that the burlesque of the Clouds was well known at the time to all parties to be meant simply in fun.39

From our knowledge of the size of the Athens of Pericles and the manners of its inhabitants, we may, of course, feel confident that any man who was at all conspicuous in such a society, as Socrates manifestly was, would meet every one else who was prominent. We cannot well doubt, for example, that Socrates must have known such men as Sophocles, Herodotus, Phidias, but it is unprofitable to speculate on his relations with such eminent contemporaries in the complete absence of all definite information.

Endnotes

1^ Apology, 17d. The MSS. vary here between ‘seventy’ and ‘over seventy.’ At Crito 52e 3, Socrates is made to give his age as ‘seventy.’

2^ Plato’s point is that Socrates jestingly compares the services he renders to his young friends by helping them to ‘deliver themselves’ of ideas with the skill of his mother. That Socrates really did speak in this way seems to be proved by the fact that in the Clouds, a play produced when Plato was an infant, Aristophanes has a joke about the ‘miscarriage of a notion’ (Clouds 137). This would be silly unless it is a parody of some way of speaking the audience would recognize as characteristically Socratic.

3^ Plato, Euthyphro 10c seems certainly to be the way in which the connection with Daedalus was understood by the writer of [Plato] Alcibiades I. 121a. It is not a sufficient objection that we have no other evidence of a clan of Daedalidae.

4^ At least we are told in the Phaedo (60a) that when the friends of Socrates were admitted to the prison on the last day of his life they found his wife Xanthippe already there ‘with the child.’ Xanthippe presumably had spent the night there, and had brought the child as too young to be left at home.

5^ See the description of his hardihood in the frozen trenches before Potidaea, Plato, Symposium 220a-b. Amipsias described him in the Connus (423 B.C.) as ‘born to spite the shoemakers,’ For Aristophanes’ description see Clouds, 362 ff.

6^ This ‘sign’ is what later writers call the ‘daemon’ or ‘guardian spirit’ of Socrates. Plato never speaks of it in this way. He calls it simply ‘the supernatural sign,’ or the ‘supernatural something.’ See the full account of it given by Socrates himself to his judges, Apology 31d.

7^ At Republic 496c, Socrates speaks of the ‘sign’ as a personal peculiarity of which his own is probably the one unique case.

8^ The Symposium describes Socrates as overtaken by a brief ‘rapt’ of this kind on his way to a dinner-party (Symposium 174d). In the same dialogue (220c-d) the scene before Potidaea is described by Alcibiades, who had been a witness of it.

9^ The typical ‘ironist’ of the animal world, in the language of Greek fable, is Reynard the Fox. The ‘ironical man’ of Aristode’s Ethics is the man whose conversation is made offensive by the affectation of mock-humility, insincere depreciation of himself and everything connected with himself. Both his pose and that of the braggart are contrasted by Aristotle with the straightforward veracity of the man who is candid and free from ‘self-consciousness.’

10^ See in particular Protagoras 309a, Gorgias 481d, and, above all, the narrative put into the mouth of Alcibiades himself, Symposium 217a-219d.

11^ See the words of Aeschines’ Alcibiades Fr. 4 (Krauss), where Socrates is made to compare his ‘love’ (ἔρως = eros) for Alcibiades with the Bacchic ‘possession.’

12^ Apart from frequent allusions of this kind in Plato, cf. the playful assertions to the same effect in Xenophon, Symposium viii 2, Memorabilia III. xi. 16 ff.

13^ It may be worth while to remark that the ‘corruption of the young’ with which Socrates was charged has nothing to do with this side of his relation to his juniors. It is certain both that an imputation of ‘homosexuality’ would have been an effective weapon in the hands of his accusers, and that no such imputation was made by them. The real charge, as we shall see, was that of ‘educating’ Alcibiades and Critias, and so being responsible for their offences against the democracy. I only mention the obvious point because it has been quite lately grossly misrepresented in an article in the Quarterly Review.

14^ The conversation which the Republic proposes to describe must be imagined to take place at the latest in Plato’s early childhood, if not earlier, since his eldest brother, Adimantus, who figures there as a young man, was old enough to stand in loco parentis to him in 399, as we see from Apology 34a, where Socrates mentions him as a relative who could be trusted to give an authoritative opinion on the effect of his own society upon Plato.

15^ It must be remembered that the Orphic religion was not that of any political community. It was recruited, like a modern church, by voluntary initiation in its sacraments, and was ‘international.’ The original Pythagoreans combined a similar religion based on the doctrine of the immortal soul with their science.

16^ The English reader will find the most satisfactory general sketch of the whole development down to c. 450 B.C. in Burnet’s Greek Philosophy, Pt. 1, pp. 1-101. Further details may be studied in the same author’s Early Greek Philosophy (ed. 3, 1920) or P. Tannery, Pour l’histoire de la science Hellène (ed. 2, 1930). For a brief account of the early history of mathématics see G. Loria, Histoire des sciences mathématiques dans l’antiquité Hellénique (Paris, 1929). It seems clear that by the early manhood of Socrates the Greek geometers were in possession of the substance of the contents of Euclid, i, ii, iii, iv, vi.

17^ Parmenides thought quite naively of this Absolute as a solid material sphere, but this is a mere historical incident.

18^ Zeno’s famous ‘paradoxes,’ Achilles, The Flying Arrow, and the rest, belong to this polemic. The fullest study of its importance and effects known to me is H. Hasse and H. Scholz, Die Grundlagenkrisis der Griechischen Mathematik, Berlin, 1928.

19^ The word ‘sophist’ at this date means simply what our ancestors in the age of Queen Anne called a ‘wit’ and includes theorists about cosmology as well as ‘humanists.’ We must not read into it any of the moral disparagement conveyed by our words sophist and sophistry. Isocrates and Plato between them created these implications by their adoption of the word to mean a counterfeit pretender to philosophy. In their day the itinerant ‘educators of men’ had ceased to exist.

20^ Isocrates (xv. 235) expressly says that ‘Pericles was the pupil of two sophists, Anaxagoras and Damon,’ and the same thing is implied by the well-known language of Plato in the Phaedrus (270a) about the ‘elevation’ which the oratory of Pericles owed to his association with Anaxagoras.

21^ The currently received chronology places the escape of Anaxagoras from Athens, where he had lived for thirty years, just before the outbreak of the Peloponnesian War, c. 432 B.C. But this is clearly inconsistent with the representations of Plato, who has given a long account of the hopes raised in the breast of the youthful Socrates by the Anaxagorean doctrine of Mind as the cause of the order in the Universe, and his subsequent disappointment. Plato insists on the point that Socrates only knew of the thought of Anaxagoras from reading his book (Phaedo 97b ff.), and clearly means that Anaxagoras had left Athens before Socrates was old enough to come into any personal contact with him. This fits in again with the statement that Anaxagoras had actually ‘educated’ Pericles, and with the only natural interpretation of the Alexandrian chronological notice (Diogenes Laertius, ii. 7) that he ‘began to be a philosopher at Athens in the year of Callias at the age of twenty,’ and lived there thirty years. Since the chronologists placed his birth in 500 B.C., this will mean that he came to Athens in the year of Salamis (480 B.C.) — possibly as a conscript in the army of Xerxes — and left the city c. 450. (The archon’s name Callias in our MSS. is presumably an error for Calliades, as the archon of the year of Salamis is called elsewhere.) These dates seem to be necessary, though my chronology has been called ‘impossible’ by an eminent German authority. The current account appears to be based on the fourth-century historian Ephorus, with whom chronology was a weak point.

22^ Plato, Alcibiades I. 119a mentions Pythodorus son of Isolochus and Callias son of Calliades as having each paid Zeno the high fee of 100 minae. Pythodorus, the person in whose house Plato makes Socrates meet Parmenides and Zeno, is a prominent Athenian commander of the Archidamian War, and Callias is the general who was killed before Potidaea at the opening of the war in 431 B.C., when Socrates was himself in the Athenian force.

23^ Xenophon, Memorabilia, IV. vii. 1-6. These concessions from Xenophon, which directly contradict his main thesis, can hardly mean less than that Socrates knew all that there was to be known about such subjects, though, as Xenophon says, he held that there are other things of which the knowledge is more indispensable.

24^ Phaedo 96a-100a. This passage, along with the opening pages of the Parmenides, is our most important evidence for the way in which Plato conceived of the early mental history of his hero. Since the events fall roughly rather more than twenty years before Plato’s own birth, the picture is, of course, an imaginative reconstruction, but there were plenty of members of Plato’s own family circle from whom he could derive the necessary information.

25^ Not to mention that by Plato’s own account his own early ambitions seem to have been those of the man of affairs, not those of the student (Epinomis, vii. 324b-c).

26^ It follows that Socrates was serving against a force commanded by the eminent Samian philosopher Melissus.

27^ The book was presumably written in the author’s later years, after his final removal from Athens. Hence its contents might come to Socrates as a novelty, in spite of his association with Archelaus and his school.

28^ Apology 19d, ‘should you have been told that I undertake to educate men and charge a fee for it, that is not true,’ is typical of the Platonic denials.

29^ So there might be wit and point in making Sir Oliver Lodge the hero of a similar burlesque; there would be no wit in giving such a part, say, to Mr. Chesterton. For a detailed study of the Clouds from this point of view, I may refer to the essay ‘The Phrontisterion’ in my Varia Socratica (Oxford, Parker, 1911), pp. 129 ff.

30^ Protagoras, 241a. Cf. Charmides 163d, Meno 96d, Cratylus 384b. The allusions would be pointless if they were not to an actual fact.

31^ Protagoras 361e. It is precisely because Socrates already knows Protagoras so well that his young friend in the dialogue comes to him for an introduction to the great man.

32^ Memorabilia II. i. The animosity this chapter shows against Aristippus may be a real example of the influence of Antisthenes on Xenophon. It is as a rebuke to Aristippus that Socrates relates the apologue of the Choice of Heracles, which, according to Xenophon, he took from a discourse of Prodicus.

33^ This is just where I cannot entirely follow the admirable account given by C. Bitter in his Sokrates. He fully recognizes that we have to accept Plato’s account of Socrates as well versed in all the ‘advanced science’ of his time, but suggests that this knowledge was deliberately acquired in early life as part of a deliberate preparation for the ‘mission.’ This seems to me out of keeping with Plato’s representation that the consciousness of a mission only came to Socrates in mid-life. In any case, we must not make the mistake of supposing that the ‘divine sign’ or ‘supernatural sign’ had anything to do with the matter. Plato makes no reference at all to the ‘sign’ in the part of the Apology which professes to describe the origin of the mission; when he comes to speak of the ‘sign,’ he treats it as something going back to Socrates’ childhood.

34^ Aristophanes, Birds 1553 ff., where Chaerephon’s dusky complexion is ridiculed by nicknaming him ‘the Bat.’ At Clouds 503, Socrates is made to promise old Strepsiades that the reward of diligent study in his ‘school’ will be to ‘grow just like Chaerephon,’ which provokes the startled reply, ‘Then, lack-a-mercy, I shall be a living corpse.’

35^ The attachment of Alcibiades to Socrates is described both by Plato, in the Symposium, and by Aeschines, in the remains of his Alcibiades, as going back to the boyhood of Alcibiades, who must already have been a man of at least twenty when he fought in the cavalry at Potidaea. The Charmides describes the closer introduction of Socrates to Charmides, then a mere lad, just after the campaign at Potidaea, by Critias, whose connection with Socrates is presupposed as already existing.

36^ Socrates professes to be on familiar terms with Aspasia in Plato’s Menexenus, and Aeschines wrote a dialogue on the subject of this friendship. Callias is the host who is entertaining Protagoras in Plato’s dialogue, and also a leading figure in Xenophon’s Symposium, the scene of which is laid in his house in the Piraeus in the year 421/20. He lived to a very great age, and the most prominent acts of his public career belong to the time after the death of Socrates.

37^ For the Alexandrian gossip on the relations of Socrates and Euripides see Diogenes Laertius, ii. 18, 33. How little we can trust some apparently confident assertions of this kind is shown by the fact that in one such notice (Diogenes Laertius, ii. 44) Euripides is quoted as having reproached the Athenians for the death of Socrates in his Palamedes. Since the Palamedes is parodied by Aristophanes in the Thesmophoriazusae (produced in 411 B.C.), the alleged allusion to the death of Socrates was written years before the event. Presumably the origin of the whole story is the simple fact that in Plato’s Apology (41b) Socrates refers to the story of the unjust condemnation of Palamedes as a parallel to his own case.

38^ Apology, 19c.: L. Robin, in his admirable Introduction to his edition of the Symposium (Collection des Universités de France), makes a most ingenious attempt to show that Plato’s covert purpose in his treatment of Aristophanes in the dialogue is to avenge himself on the man whom he rightly regarded as responsible for the death of Socrates by pillorying him as grand buveur et grand paillard. This seems to me, speaking with all respect, a misunderstanding of one simple phrase, that in which the art of Aristophanes is said to be ‘wholly concerned with Dionysus and Aphrodite’ (Symposium 177e). Dionysus is mentioned here as the patron of the drama, and Aphrodite, I take it, in allusion to her association with the Graces, a compliment to the ‘charm’ which is so real a feature of Aristophanic poetry.

39^ Plato makes Socrates say as much in the Apology itself (18d), where he clearly distinguishes the comic poets themselves from other persons who repeated their witticisms ‘out of spite and to misrepresent me.’

Top ↑


Chapter III. The Later Life of Socrates: His Trial And Death

If our attempted reconstruction of the life of Socrates during the period of which we know least has been successful, we have to think of him down to the age of forty as one of the most outstanding ‘intellectuals’ of a great age of mental and moral ferment, distinguished in the circles specially interested in things of the mind by a profound concern for the unseen moral order and a religious faith not common in the society around him in God and the immortal soul, as well as by a highly original view of the nature of the problems of philosophy and the methods by which they should be approached, and naturally thought of by the wider public as an amusing eccentric, a combination of pedant, paradox-monger, free-thinker, and necromancer, the character he wears in the Clouds of Aristophanes. We have to describe now the way in which his new-found activity as the preacher of a mission to all sorts and conditions of men, exercised during the years of a ‘world-war’ which gradually hardened for Athens into a fight for bare existence, led to an increasing tension between the prophet and the mass of ordinary well-meaning citizens, and finally to his condemnation on what was really a charge of incivisme, disloyalty to the spirit of Athenian life. We must, of course, not forget that though the long struggle began as a war for the maintenance of a powerful empire, and though at the ‘Peace of Nicias’ (421 B.C.), which suspended serious hostilities for two or three years, Athens, at any rate, emerged as still the most powerful of Hellenic cities, the later years of the contest, especially after the hopeless failure of the great Athenian adventure against Syracuse (in 413 B.C.), saw the imperial city fighting with her ‘back to the wall,’ and ended in the complete collapse of the old moral, political, and economic order. The well-meaning but short-sighted democrats who prosecuted Socrates were living in conditions very different from those of the secure and powerful, and therefore tolerant, democracy depicted in the Funeral Oration of Thucydides’ Peticles.

Little is recorded of the external events of the life of Socrates during the first ten years of the struggle, those of the ‘Archidamian War,’ beyond a few facts relating to his excellent military record. But it must have been at this time of his life that he married the only wife he is known to have had, Xanthippe, since we know from Plato that at the time of his death he left one son who was a lad, i.e. not more than seventeen or eighteen, and two small children, the youngest of whom appears to have been an infant in arms.1 The names of Xanthippe and of her eldest and youngest sons suggest good birth. The Alexandrian biographers represented Xanthippe as a shrew with an ungovernable temper and a foul tongue, but no hint of the kind is found in either Plato or Xenophon. In the Phaedo, the only place where Plato mentions her, she appears simply as an affectionate wife with whom Socrates has a prolonged last interview immediately before his death, and Xenophon records nothing of her except that her eldest son thought her, as sons often think a good mother, over-bearing,2 and that Antisthenes apparently did not like her.3 Presumably, then, Socrates only contracted the marriage in midlife. The Alexandrians had a story that he had also another wife, Myrto, said to be a relative of the great Aristides. But their stories about Myrto are contradictory. They make her sometimes the daughter, sometimes the granddaughter, of Aristides, sometimes the first wife of Socrates, sometimes the second. Sometimes they even assert that Socrates was married to both wives at once — apparently an invention of the scandal-monger Aristoxenus — and even tell a foolish tale that he took a second wife to comply with an imaginary Athenian statute providing for the repair of the loss of population due to the war by the legalization of bigamy.4 (It would be chronologically possible that Socrates should have been twice married, but the silence of Plato and Xenophon makes it unlikely that he was.)

The military service of Socrates, so far as we are informed about it, belongs — apart from the probable early participation in the blockade of Samos under Pericles — to the Archidamian War. Plato relates that he distinguished himself by exceptional bravery at the siege of Potidaea (431-430 B.C.), and again on the disastrous field of Delium (424 B.C.), where the whole military force of Athens was routed by the Boeotians. A third campaign, before Amphipolis, mentioned by Plato (Apology 28e) is commonly supposed to refer to the action outside that city in 422 B.C., in which both the Athenian and the Spartan commanders, Cleon and Brasidas, lost their lives, though Professor Burnet has suggested that the reference may be rather to the fighting which accompanied the foundation of Amphipolis, some fifteen years earlier. It is clear from Plato’s accounts that Socrates’ record for military courage and presence of mind stood very high. He is made to refer to his exemplary behaviour as a soldier with justifiable pride in the Apology (loc. cit.), and elsewhere Plato has put an encomium on his conduct both before Potidaea and at Delium into the mouth of a most competent eye-witness. In the Symposium (219e ff.) after praising Socrates’ endurance of all the hardships of the rigorous campaign, and relating the story of his remarkable ‘trance,’ Alcibiades records that in the fighting he was himself defended when wounded by Socrates, and says that the prize for valour — the equivalent of our V.C. — awarded to himself by the commanders, ought in justice to have gone to the older man. He adds that he was a witness of Socrates’ presence of mind in the disastrous retirement after Delium, and that his self-command far surpassed that of his companion in the retreat, the general Laches. In the Laches (181b), Laches himself is made to tell the story, with the comment that if the rest of the Athenian force had behaved like Socrates, the defeat would have been turned into a victory.5 Plato evidently means us to understand that Socrates was highly esteemed as a good soldier by the professional military men, and this, no doubt, helps to account for the regard felt for him at a later date by young men who aspired to a military career, like Xenophon and Xenophon’s bête noire, the Thessalian condottiere Meno, after whom one of Plato’s dialogues is named.

We have no record of any particular acts of Socrates between the retreat from Delium and the very last years of the renewed struggle, when Athens was making her final effort to avoid complete defeat. But we have to remember that it is just the years between the Peace of Nicias and the general renewal of war with the Spartan occupation of Decelea, a post in Athenian territory, in 413 which must have been most critical for his position. It was in these years that Alcibiades became the darling of the militant Athenian Imperialists, and inspired them with the fatal dream of the conquest of Syracuse which led directly to the undoing of Athens herself. The date of the party in the house of Agathon described in Plato’s Symposium is laid early in 415, in the months just before the sailing of the great Athenian flotilla with Alcibiades as its principal commander; and Plato’s picture of the commander ‘flown with insolence and wine’ is, no doubt, meant also to recall the mood of general buoyant self-confidence in which the Athenian people were then indulging.6 In a few months, the whole situation had changed. The great Armada had hardly been dispatched before Athens was convulsed by a gigantic ‘religious scandal.’ Alcibiades himself and many of his associates were accused of having repeatedly taken part in sacrilegious burlesques of the Eleusinian mysteries, an integral part of the religious worship of the State. Alcibiades was promptly recalled to stand his trial, made his escape on his way home, and was capitally condemned in his absence, along with his uncle Axiochus, also a member of the Socratic circle, and a large number of other distinguished men, apparently including several of those who figure in Plato’s account of Agathon’s banquet.7

Alcibiades made his way to Sparta and became at once the most formidable enemy of the democracy who had worshipped him. It was by his advice that, when the Spartans renewed hostilities, they took a step which changed the character of the whole war, the establishment of a permanent fortified post on Attic territory. Alcibiades was now openly a traitor as well as a man capitally condemned and religiously cursed for sacrilege, and Socrates must lie henceforth, in the minds of many worthy citizens, under the imputation of being responsible for the misdeeds of his supposed ‘pupil.’ It is true that after the failure of the anti-democratic coup d’état of the year 411 — the so-called ‘oligarchy of the Four Hundred’ — Alcibiades began to work for his fellow-citizens instead of against them, and was actually for a time recalled to Athens in triumph (407 B.C.), but the tide of popular favour soon turned, and he was once more in exile and general ill-repute when Socrates, for the first time in his life, suddenly emerged as an actor on the scene of public affairs.

This was in the autumn of the year 406 B.C. In the summer the Athenians had saved themselves at the eleventh hour from final defeat by a great naval victory off the islets of Arginusae, between Lesbos and the Asiatic mainland. But the victory had cost 25 vessels and the lives of 4000 men, many of whom, it was believed, might have been rescued but for the culpable negligence of the commanders. It was resolved to try the generals who had been in command for their lives, by the process known at Athens as eisangelia,8 and the prosecution further demanded that the fate of all the eight commanders incriminated should be decided en bloc by a single vote. As this was a direct infringement of the normal constitutional procedure, the prytanes, the Committee of the Senate of Five Hundred whose business it was to prepare the agenda of the Assembly and preside in its meetings, to their honour protested strongly, and declared that they could put no such illegal proposal to the vote. Though the ‘sign’ of Socrates refused to allow him to imperil his mission by mixing in politics, this had not prevented him from serving the city in its extremity by allowing himself to be nominated for the Senate, and he was, as it happened, a member of the Committee of prytanes on this occasion. After a long and heated discussion, the resistance of the other prytanes was overcome by the threat of the prosecutors to include their names in the indictment; Socrates remained unmoved, but his solitary protest was overborne. The generals were tried and condemned in a body, and the six of them who were actually in the hands of the authorities promptly executed; but Socrates was entitled to tell the story, as he did at his own trial, in proof of his sterling integrity and fearless devotion to the cause of law.9

In the unhappy months of the year 404/3 which followed upon the capitulation of Athens to Lysander, Socrates had the opportunity to show that he was no more to be intimidated by an oligarchical camarilla than by a canaille. Athens had surrendered at discretion, and the brutal Spartan whom the fortune of war, or not improbably the treachery of her own commander, had made master of the situation had no notion of permitting the continuation of the democracy. Under pressure from Lysander a Commission of Thirty was appointed, with instructions to draw up a legislation for the future government of the city. Unfortunately, instead of performing the task assigned them, they constituted themselves a violently oligarchical revolutionary government, forced the more radical democrats to leave the city and establish themselves in the port of Piraeus, and proceeded to disgrace themselves by a great number of arbitrary executions and confiscations of property, until they were forcibly expelled, and a modern democracy re-established, in the course of the year 403. It was Socrates’ misfortune that two of his close associates were prominent in this disgraceful business — Critias, cousin of Plato’s mother, who was the leader of the most violent party among the ‘Thirty,’ and Charmides, her brother, who was one of the principal agents. Again, as in the case of Alcibiades, there was the appearance that Socrates was ‘educating traitors.’10 He was not himself, with all his respect for constituted authority, in sympathy with the kind of democracy which had grown up after the death of Pericles, and, unlike his old friend Chaerephon, felt no call to leave Athens when the advanced democrats withdrew to the Piraeus. The temporary masters of the city, however, knew well enough that he was certain to criticize their procedure in the same trenchant way in which he had been accustomed to speak his mind about all public affairs. They took occasion of his caustic comments on their first irregular executions11 to cite him before themselves and forbid him to converse with younger men, on the pretext that he was contravening one of their decrees which prohibited the teaching of the art of speaking. Socrates countered with some characteristically humorous remarks about the impossibility of obeying such an injunction and was dismissed with a menace by Critias.12 It was a more serious act of intimidation that the attempt was next made to implicate Socrates himself in one of these administrative murders.13 He, with four others, received express orders to arrest Leon of Salamis, a wealthy man whose property it was intended to confiscate. The others performed the task, and Leon was duly murdered, but Socrates went straight home, though he expected to pay for the disobedience with his life, but for the counter-revolution which ended the Terror (Plato, Apology, 32c-d).

It was the distrust aroused by Socrates’ connection with ‘traitors’ which caused the leaders of the restored democracy to bring him to trial in the year 400/399. Alcibiades and Critias were both dead, but the democrats did not feel safe while the man who was imagined to have inspired their treasons was still an influence in public life. Anytus, son of Anthemion, the instigator of the proceedings, seems to have had no unworthy motive, nor was he a political or religious fanatic. In politics he was a moderate democrat and a chief promoter of the amnesty between the conflicting factions after the downfall of the ‘Thirty,’ proving his loyalty to it by refusal to seek any compensation for grave personal losses under the usurpation. He was no religious fanatic, for in the year in which he supported the prosecution of Socrates for ‘impiety’ he was also aiding the defence of the orator Andocides, then on trial on the same charge. Nor had he any desire to shed blood. The object of demanding the death sentence was merely to induce Socrates to consult his own safety by withdrawing into exile and letting the case go by default14 It has been asked why the prosecution was delayed until the fourth year after the restoration of the democracy. The explanation is that the revolution and counter-revolution of 404/3 had brought the ordinary work of the law-courts into confusion; the whole body of Attic law had to be revised and codified, and the Commission appointed for the work did not finish its task until the year 401/400. This is why the proceedings against Socrates could not be set on foot until 400;15 in point of fact, Anytus made his move as soon as it was really practicable.

A prominent moderate politician like Anytus could not, of course, appear as the actual prosecutor in a case of this kind; this task was assigned to an obscure and comparatively youthful person called Meletus (probably not the poet of that name who is mentioned by Aristophanes in the Frogs, though he may have been this man’s son). The prosecutor of Andocides for ‘impiety’ was also called Meletus, and had been one of the party who executed the illegal arrest of Leon. What appears to be the speech delivered by Meletus against Andocides has been preserved for us in the collection ascribed to Lysias, and it is the utterance of an extravagant religious fanatic. If, as is most probable, it was the same man who prosecuted Socrates, this will explain at once why ‘impiety’ was selected as the formal charge. This would ensure that the tool of Anytus should do his work with a will. It is the worst feature in the conduct of Anytus that, to effect what he believed a salutary purpose, he should have used an instrument whom he must have despised. His own part in the proceedings was confined to the delivery of a formal speech in support of the prosecution. A similar part was played by a third speaker, Lycon, of whom nothing is known, except that Socrates in Plato’s Apology speaks of him as a professional ‘orator.’

As the offence with which it was resolved to charge Socrates was technically one against the State religion, the case fell under the cognizance of the official known at Athens as the King, the second of the nine annual magistrates called collectively the ‘archons,’ religion being specially his province. His business was, in the first instance, to see that the indictment was in proper legal form, to enter the reply of the accused to the charge, take the depositions of the witnesses on either side,16 and make the other necessary preliminary arrangements for the bringing of the case before a popular jury. In the actual trial the King had further to preside over the proceedings, but it is important to remember that he had not the functions of a British judge. He could neither comment on the evidence nor rule out as irrelevant any matter introduced by either party. The jurors themselves were at once ‘judges of the law’ and ‘judges of the fact,’ as well as judges on the question of what is relevant evidence. Since they were a numerous body — Socrates, as we shall see, appears to have been tried by a body of 500 — only assigned to the case they were to decide by sortition at the opening of the proceedings, and voted by secret ballot, a trial before such a court was virtually one before a ‘public meeting,’ and this has to be borne in mind in reading Plato’s account of the defence.

We do not, of course, know what the charge against Socrates as originally formulated by Meletus was, as the official record would preserve only the final version in which it was transmitted to the Court by the King for adjudication. In Plato’s dialogue Euthyphro, the date of which is laid during the preliminary proceedings, Socrates is made to say that Meletus is prosecuting him as a ‘maker of novel gods’,17 but nothing is said of this in the various accounts of the indictment preferred at the actual trial. The most accurate of these is probably that given in Diogenes Laertius,18 which appears to be a transcript of the actual document as still preserved in the second century A.D. ‘Meletus, son of Meletus, of the deme of Pitthus, indicts Socrates, son of Sophroniscus, of the deme Alopece, on his oath, to the following effect. Socrates is guilty (1) of not worshipping the gods whom the State worships, but introducing new and unfamiliar religious practices; (2) and, further, of corrupting the young. The prosecutor demands the death penalty.’19

We must be careful not to misunderstand either clause of the indictment. It is certain that the first charge does not mean that Socrates holds what we call ‘heretical opinions.’ nor yet that he disbelieves the stories of the conventional mythology, as he frequently confesses in Plato’s dialogues that he disbelieves them. The religion of the Athenian State was wholly a matter of worship, or cultus; it had no theological dogmas and no sacred books. And it is certain that it was no offence against religion to disbelieve in the mythology of Homer and the poets; the current view of this was that the poets invented their stories for the entertainment of their public.20 It is also clear that the charge of ‘novel religious practices’ has nothing to do with the ‘supernatural sign’ of Socrates. From the point of view of the average Athenian, that would be only a case of the familiar fact of ‘possession,’ and it is also plain from Plato’s Apology21 that no reference was made to the matter at the trial until Socrates raised it himself. In fact, as Plato represents things, no one, not even the prosecutor himself, knew what this part of the accusation really meant. If we read between the lines, however, we may fairly discover in Plato’s Apology both what was in the mind of Meletus and why he could not make himself more intelligible.

In Plato, Socrates deals with the charge in a curious way. He says nothing whatever to disprove the accusation of ‘introducing novel religious practices,’ and contrives to entrap Meletus into explaining that the phrase about not worshipping the gods of the State is meant as an imputation of sheer atheism. He can then, of course, point with triumph to the incompatibility of the two parts of the accusation (Apology 26b-27c). It is easy to see that this is no more than a legitimate employment of humour to silence an accuser who either cannot, or dare not, explain his own real meaning. What his meaning was is indicated by an earlier section of the Platonic Apology (18a-19d), in which Socrates maintains that, for want of anything more specific to allege against him, the prosecution is falling back on the stock accusations against ‘wits’ and men of science as a class, and trusting to the caricature of himself as a man of that kind in Aristophanes’ Clouds (now a quarter of a century old). The point is that the Ionian men of science had been accustomed to use the name ‘god’ in a wholly non-religious way for ‘air,’ or whatever else they held to be the eternal substance of which things are made. This is why Aristophanes had made Socrates say that ‘the gods’ were not ‘current coin’ in his school, and had represented him as teaching that Zeus has been dethroned by ‘vortex-motion.’ and swearing by a set of ‘deities of his own mintage,’ Chaos, Respiration, Aether, the Clouds.22 Socrates means, in fact, that the charge of ‘atheism’ is based on nothing more than an attempt to prejudice the Court by reminding it of the general reputation of the old Ionian science. (Possibly, also, though nothing is said which throws any light on this in the Apology, Meletus may have counted upon the recollection of the old scandal of 415 about the ‘profanation of the mysteries,’ in which Alcibiades and other friends of Socrates had been involved; and he may even have reckoned with the possibility that some of the jurors would know that, in the more recent past, Socrates had been in intercourse with young Pythagorean admirers from cities which had only just ceased to be ‘enemy states.’) It now becomes clear why the prosecutor could not explain himself more frankly. By the terms of the Amnesty which had put an end to the confusion of the year 404/3, no citizen could be called upon to answer for offences committed before that date, and no charge founded upon alleged acts committed at an earlier time could be entertained by the Court. It would be the business of Anytus, as a chief promoter of the Amnesty, to see that its conditions were not explicitly contravened.

The meaning of the second charge, ‘corruption of the young,’ is clearer. At the actual trial, indeed, the prosecutor and his supporters seem to have left their meaning vague. At least, Socrates is represented by Plato as professing to be much puzzled as to the particular kind of harm he is accused of doing to his younger associates. He says it can neither be teaching them the kind of ‘nonsense’ about natural science which he is made to talk in the play of Aristophanes, nor exercising the calling of a professional sophist. It is notorious to every one that he has never been a professional ‘educator,’ nor had a ‘pupil,’ and no less notorious that the scientific speculations burlesqued by Aristophanes are not the subject of his conversations. If his prosecutors would be candid, they would have to confess that the alleged harm done to the young men who enjoy listening to his cross-examination of his fellow-citizens really means the exposure of the self-satisfied ignorance of their elders. Reading between the lines, one gathers that what really annoyed Anytus was that the criticisms of Socrates on the incompetence of politicians like himself tended to lower their reputation and to produce a critical attitude of mind towards the democracy and its institutions among the acuter of the younger generation — as was certainly the fact (Apology 19d-20c, 23c-e, 24c-26b). We might fairly infer that something worse than this must have been the real gravamen of the accusation, but that the prosecutors had reasons for not putting it into plain words.

What they chiefly meant we can still see if we turn to the Memorabilia of Xenophon, a defence of the memory of Socrates against a written attack by an ‘accuser,’ who is apparently the sophist Polycrates, an undistinguished writer who seems, a few years after the trial, to have worked up the case of Anytus and Meletus into literary form. Xenophon also mentions one or two minor ways in which the ‘accuser’ misrepresented the character of Socrates. He charged him with teaching young men to make light of the respect due to the older generation, and with extracting an immoral sense from passages of the poets.23 But the particular ‘accusation’ which Xenophon is most anxious to refute is something much more precise. The ‘accuser’ charged Socrates with educating Critias and Alcibiades, and Xenophon argues at great length that both only associated with Socrates long enough to learn something of his unparalleled skill in speech, which they abused to their own ends.24 Any reference to this alleged influence on the two great ‘traitors’ at the trial itself was banned by the Amnesty of 404/3, and Anytus, no doubt, took care that the accusation should be left obscure. This is why we do not at once see the point of the reference when Socrates in Plato very pointedly denies that he has ever had an actual ‘pupil.’25 Polycrates, in his pamphlet, blurted out what the forms of legal procedure would only allow Meletus to hint at. We see from Isocrates that he charged Socrates in so many words with being the teacher of Alcibiades. Isocrates replies by denying the fact, exactly as Plato makes Socrates himself do.26 He must also have said the same thing about Critias, and this explains why fifty years later the orator Aeschines could remind the Athenians that ‘you put Socrates to death because he had been the teacher of Critias.’27 The motives for the prosecution are unintelligible unless it is understood that Anytus honestly held Socrates and his teaching responsible for the mischief done to Athens by the man who had taught the enemy where to strike a deadly blow at her, and the man who had been the leader in the Terror which followed her downfall. No doubt the distrust of Anytus was provoked by the sort of unsparing criticism on all the famous statesmen of the democracy of which Socrates often delivers himself in Plato’s dialogues; almost certainly he had had his personal experiences of the humiliating effects of cross-examination by Socrates, but the real secret of his hostility lay deeper. Socrates had not, in fact, educated the two men who had done most to ruin their native city, but it was his misfortune that he had been a friend of both, and was inevitably supposed to have been something more.28

To the general surprise, Socrates did not go into voluntary exile, but remained quietly at Athens to await the trial, which came on in the spring or early summer of the year 399. No doubt, from his strictly constitutionalist point of view, the State had a right to hold an inquisition into the character of a citizen, and it was the citizen’s simple duty to face the investigation. His defence has been preserved by Plato, who was present in court. The speech is so characteristic that we may be confident that Plato’s version has reproduced it with close accuracy.29 Socrates did not court death; on the contrary, he said plainly that he desired an honourable acquittal, provided only that acquittal involved no compromise with the truth.30 On his relations with Alcibiades and Critias he was careful, as loyalty to the spirit of the Amnesty required him to be, to say nothing beyond the one simple fact that he had never been any man’s ‘master.’ The popular misconceptions about himself he explained as due to reminiscences of the burlesques of Aristophanes and the other comic poets. As to the charge of ‘novel religious practices’ and ‘neglect to worship the gods,’ he was content to show that Meletus himself either would not, or could not, explain what it meant. The allegation of being a ‘corrupter of the young’ he treated a little more seriously, though still quite lightly, and offered to rebut it by calling the elder relatives of Plato and other young companions in disproof of it. If his object had been, as it was not, merely to secure an acquittal on any terms, he should then have gone on to say something about his excellent military record, and his courageous defiance of Critias in the matter of Leon of Salamis, and there the matter might have ended. But such a defence would have been an act of treason to his mission. Accordingly, he made no attempt to avoid the odium always attaching in the suspicious Athenian democracy to the reputation of superior ‘cleverness.’ He made the story of the oracle which had declared him the wisest of men the centre of his whole speech, and described without concealment the way in which it had led him to take up the work of convincing all and sundry, from the leading statesmen downwards, of their disgraceful ignorance of the one kind of knowledge which is of supreme moment, knowledge how to make one’s own soul and those of others as good as possible. To desist from this mission, he said, would be rebellion against God, and the Court might rest assured that nothing short of death would deter him from prosecuting it. Even the military record and die affair of Leon were brought into the speech merely to explain how impossible dereliction of plain duty would be in the speaker, and the story of the defiance of Critias was joined to that of the equally bold defiance of the democracy itself in the trial of the Arginusae generals. It is not surprising, therefore, that the Court found a verdict of guilty, though by a small majority. When we take into account the tone of the speech and the fact that the jury were, to all intents and purposes, a public meeting, the result, so far, is creditable to their liberality of mind rather than otherwise.31

Socrates had now to propose a penalty for himself as an alternative to that of death. Every one must have supposed that he would propose banishment, and it is plain that if he had done so, the Court would have been satisfied. But here again he was true to his own principles. He held, he said, that his mission had been a God-given benefit to Athens, and that his deserts would properly be recognized by conferring on him the exceptional privilege, given to victors at the Olympic games, eminent generals, and a few others, of a seat for life at the public table in the Prytaneum. Holding this view, he could not conscientiously propose to inflict banishment, or any other real evil, on himself. A mere fine, however, is no evil, so long as a man has the money to pay it, and Socrates was free in conscience to offer to pay such a fine. Accordingly, he offered to pay such a sum as he could immediately raise, 1 mina,32 adding immediately that Crito, Plato, and other friends had prevailed on him to raise the offer to 30 minae, for which they were ready to give security. It is natural enough that the jurors should have been irritated by this uncompromising speech into voting the death penalty by a larger majority33 than that which had found the verdict of guilty.

According to both Plato and Xenophon, Socrates, at this stage, addressed a few final words to the minority among the judges who had pronounced throughout in his favour. Xenophon makes him do little more than repeat his declaration of innocence, but Plato’s version adds something more characteristic. The sentence which has been passed upon him, he says, is no evil. At worst, death is no more than an unbroken rest, and so no bad thing. But there is a different belief, and it is made clear that it is his own, that death for a good man is an entry on a better life. In that case, Socrates may expect the happiness of coming before the righteous and all-wise judges of the dead, who will certainly reverse the decision of a misinformed and prejudiced Court, and of meeting with the famous men of older days, including some who, like himself, have been unjustly condemned by their contemporaries; and there will be no danger there that his vocation of cross-examining his company will be cut short by another sentence of death.34 If this is the fate to which the Court is consigning him, they are unintentionally conferring the greatest of benefits on him.

The usual practice at Athens was that a condemned man was delivered at once to the ‘eleven’ who had to administer the law, and that his execution followed within some twenty-four hours. The case of Socrates was an exception. There was a custom that a ‘sacred boat’ should be despatched annually to the shrine of Apollo in Delos, in memory of the prehistoric deliverance by Theseus from the tribute of ‘seven lads and seven maidens’ imposed by Minos of Cnossus. The city was religiously purified before the despatch of the boat, and the rules of ceremonial purity forbade any executions to be carried out until it had returned. It so happened that this period of ritual purity had begun in 399, the day before the case of Socrates came on for trial, and it was therefore necessary to decide what must be done with him. (The matter could not have been dealt with until the sentence had been given, since no one, of course, expected that Socrates, if convicted, would propose anything but banishment for himself.) The wealthy Crito did his best to induce the Court to allow Socrates to remain at liberty until the return of the ‘sacred boat,’ undertaking to give security that there should be no attempt at escape,35 but the offer was rejected. Socrates was accordingly committed to the prison of the ‘eleven,’ where he was kept in chains of some kind, though not prevented from enjoying the daily company of his friends. As the boat was detained for a month36 by contrary winds, the whole of this period was spent in these daily colloquies, and it appears that some of the philosopher’s foreign friends, such as Phaedo of Elis and the young Thebans, Simmias and Cebes, stayed permanently in Athens throughout this time. Socrates also amused himself by taking to verse-making for the first time in his life. He composed a Paean to Apollo, and versified fables of Aesop.37 He accounted for this by saying that all through life he had been haunted by a dream in which he was commanded to ‘practise music.’ In the past he had supposed that the meaning of the injunction was that he should labour on his ‘mission,’ since ‘philosophy is the truest music.’ Since the dream was repeated during his imprisonment, when the mission could no longer be exercised, piety bade him to comply with its directions in their literal sense.

Socrates’ friends made a final attempt to save him by corrupting his guardians to connive at escape. All the preparations had been made, and, to obviate any reluctance the philosopher might feel to implicate fellow-citizens in an affair which might have unpleasant consequences for them, Theban admirers, on whom the Attic authorities could have no hold, were prepared to provide all the necessary funds (Crito 45b). Socrates, true to his character, refused to avail himself of the opportunity, and the reason for his refusal is explained in Plato’s Crito. It is that escape would stultify the professed principles of a lifetime. The verdict of the Court which had sentenced him to death was false in fact, and had been procured by misrepresentations discreditable to the prosecutors. But it was the legal finding of a legitimately constituted Court, and the State had therefore a right to its enforcement. The wrong committed against Socrates had been committed not by Athens, but by Anytus and Meletus; if Socrates should break prison, this would be a crime against the State and its laws themselves, an act of treason against the spirit of citizenship. Socrates had all the loyalty to conscience of a modern ‘conscientious objector,’ combined with a respect for the ‘public conscience’ which is, unfortunately, unusual in such quarters.

The story of his last day on earth, as related in the Phaedo by Plato, who, though not himself present, had the fullest means of getting information from those who were, and was writing to be read by them, is perhaps the greatest thing in the prose literature of Europe. Socrates, who had been warned of the exact day of his departure two days earlier ‘in a dream,’ was found by his friends in company with his wife and her child, whom he sent home at once, apparently for necessary rest. (Xanthippe and the baby seem to have been spending the night in the prison.) He bore himself with his usual gay constancy — ‘merriment’ was as native to him as to Thomas More — and spoke much of his conviction that death, to a good man, is the rise of the curtain on a drama for which his whole life has been a rehearsal — the drama of the soul’s liberation from confinement in the ‘pound’ or ‘pen’ of the body, where it has hitherto been confined by God, for His own good purposes, into the greater freedom of a better world, where truth and reality will be known face to face, and no longer ‘peeped’ at ‘through lattices of eyes.’ A life spent in ‘philosophy’ — the pursuit of truth for its own sake — is itself one long preparation for this blissful enlargement, as it is also the true service of God, who requires us simply to ‘make the soul’ — that within us which thinks and knows — ‘as good as possible.’ Since he had spent his own life in this service of God, he said, he could look forward with confidence to the future awaiting him. Finding that his young friends from Thebes, Cebes and Simmias, were much troubled with ‘scientific’ doubts that the soul may be no more than a perishable function of the body, he devoted his last morning to reasoning with them in his own justification, on the ‘real distinction of the soul from the body,’ and the grounds for believing that it is neither born with the body nor dies with it, but shares in the eternity of the Truth and Goodness which it knows. Through the whole discussion he showed himself free alike from depression by the prospect of imminent death, and from over-anxiety to cling to a comforting belief without giving full weight to all there might be to urge against it.

The argument finished — it ended with an imaginative picture of the doom of the good and the wicked in the unseen world — Socrates retired to prepare his own body for its funeral, that the necessary offices might not have to be done by others upon his corpse, and to hold a last private interview with the ‘children and women of his family.’ It must have been a long interview, for the darkness was already closing in on the spring or summer day when he returned to his friends. At sunset the ‘officer of the eleven’ — as we should say, ‘the governor of the prison’ — took a formal farewell, not without tears, of the ‘bravest, gentlest, best’ man who had ever been committed to him. Then appeared the actual minister of death, bearing the draught of poison38 by which the condemned were executed at Athens. Socrates took the bowl with composure, and would have made a ‘libation’ as a grace before drinking, but for the warning that the quantity of the potion prepared would admit of no waste. With a few words of prayer for a ‘happy passing,’ he drained the cup without any sign of repugnance. At this point the composure of the company of friends broke down; several of them were openly weeping, and one, Apollodorus, was so hysterical that he had to be recalled to decorum by Socrates himself. On the instructions of the prison official Socrates walked about the room for a time, until his feet began to feel heavy; then he lay down on his pallet and covered his head. Manual exploration showed that a numbness was gradually advancing upwards towards the region of the heart. After an interval of silence the old man uncovered his head for a moment with the request, ‘Crito, we owe a cock to Asclepius; do not forget to pay the debt.’ These were his last words. Was he recollecting dimly some incident, connected perhaps with an infantile illness in his family? Or did he promise the gift to the god of healing because he hoped to wake from the fever of life cured? A little later there was a convulsive movement; the body was uncovered and life found to be gone. ‘Hereupon Crito closed his eyes and mouth, and so ended our friend, the man we hold best, wisest, most upright of his age.’

The Alexandrians told stories of the remorse which fell upon the Athenians, how they put Meletus to death and honoured Socrates with a statue. But these tales have long been recognized to be fabulous. Socrates was feared by certain prominent politicians of the restored democracy as the supposed instigator of Alcibiades and Critias, and these politicians desired to get him out of Athens. But there was no wish to take his life, and he can never have been the mark of general hostility. Nearly forty-five percent, of his judges, as we have seen, were for acquitting him. And there was no general revulsion of feeling after his death; public sentiment remained divided about Socrates, as about Alcibiades himself. This is shown by the language used by Isocrates, who had known him, though not as an intimate. Isocrates tells Polycrates that when he charged Socrates in his pamphlet with having been the preceptor of Alcibiades he was saying what was not true, but had it been true, would have been a still greater compliment to the memory of Socrates than any paid it by ‘those who are accustomed to eulogize him.’39 Socrates owes his immortality of fame as the martyr of philosophy not to any melodramatic outburst of popular sentiment on the part of an emotional democracy, but to the Providence which gave him as younger friend and follower the one man in history who has combined supreme greatness as a philosophic thinker with equal greatness as a master of language, and so has been, directly or indirectly, the teacher of all thinking men since his own day.

Endnotes

1^ The name of the eldest son, recorded by Xenophon, was Lamprocles, those of the others, Sophroniscus and Menexenus.

2^ Memorabilia II. ii., where Socrates reproves his son for his ungrateful attitude.

3^ Symposium ii. 10. This dislike may account for the origin of the later gossip.

4^ For this worthless Alexandrian gossip see Diogenes Laertius, ii. 26, Athenaeus, xiii. 556d.

5^ In Diogenes Laertius, ii. 26, Socrates is said to have saved the life of Xenophon at Delium, but since Xenophon was certainly an infant at the time, this must be merely an inaccurate version of the saving of Alcibiades at Potidaea.

6^ We cannot, of course, say whether this ‘banquet’ was a real historical event, though I should imagine it probably was. In any case, Plato has been careful to adapt the tone of his description to the state of feeling at the time.

7^ The fullest account — of course an ex parte one — of the whole scandal is that given by the orator Andocides — himself an incriminated party who had turned informer — in his speech On the Mysteries. It can hardly be a mere coincidence that three of the accused bear the same names as persons familiar to us from the Symposium, Phaedrus, Eryximachus (both speakers in the dialogue), and Acumenus, the father of the latter.

8^ This meant that the case was judged not by a sworn jury but by a vote of the citizen assembly. Thus it was analogous to a ‘Bill of Attainder.’

9^ Plato’s account of the matter will be found at Apology, 32b-c; Xenophon tells the history of the trial at length in Hellenica, 1. vii. Plato was probably, and Xenophon almost equally probably, an eyewitness of the proceedings. It is not quite clear from either narrative whether the scene in which all the other prytanes were intimidated into withdrawing their opposition took place in the Assembly itself or in the Senate. Referring to the event in the Memorabilia (I. i. 18), Xenophon says that Socrates was actually Chairman of the Committee of the prytanes. Nothing is said of this in his own much fuller narrative in the Hellenica, nor in Plato, and it is likely that he has made a slip of memory, as he certainly has, in the same sentence, in giving the number of the condemned generals as nine, whereas only eight were condemned, and only six actually put to death. The allusion in the Gorgias to an occasion where Socrates was Chairman of such a Committee and made some technical blunder in taking a vote (Gorgias, 474a) seems to be to some much earlier event. It is certain that a man could be a member of the Athenian Senate more than once. For the details of this cause célèbre see Grote, History of Greece, c. lxiv.

10^ It is only fair to remember that these men probably ‘lost their heads’ under the temptation presented by their situation. Critias had previously been known as a poet and a man of wide culture whose political leanings were decidedly democratic. If Xenophon is to be trusted — though he was too young to be speaking on the point from personal knowledge — it was Socrates himself who first encouraged Charmides to conquer his natural bashfulness and take part in politics (Memorabilia III. vii. 1).

11^ He had observed that he had never before known a herdsman plume himself on his skill in diminishing the number of his cattle (Xenophon, Memorabilia I. ii. 32).

12^ See the full story in Xenophon, Memorabilia, I. ii. 32-38.

13^ This, says Plato, was a common proceeding with the ‘Thirty.’ They were anxious to protect themselves against a day of reckoning by associating as many persons as possible in their criminality.

14^ This is what is meant by the words of Anytus quoted at Apology 29c, that either Socrates should never have faced the Court or the death penalty should be insisted on.

15^ See the full explanation of the point in Burnet’s note to Plato, Euthyphro 4c 4.

16^ Witnesses were neither examined nor cross-examined in court; the evidence consisted of written records of what had been deposed in the preliminary stages, and no fresh matter could be introduced. Each party was, however, allowed to put questions to the antagonist, which had to be answered.

17^ Euthyphro 3b. Presumably either the King declined to entertain the charge in this form, or Anytus induced Meletus to reduce it to the vaguer accusation of ‘novel religious rites.’

18^ Diogenes Laertius, ii. 40. The authority alleged is Favorinus of Arles, a well-known scholar of the reign of Hadrian, who seems to have seen the original document. Plato and Xenophon agree with this as to the counts of the indictment, but Plato puts the charge of ‘corruption of the young’ first, probably because it was the one treated more seriously by Socrates in his defence.

19^ The case was of a kind common in Attic procedure in which the prosecutor proposed one penalty, and the accused, if convicted, a milder one. The Court had to adopt one of the proposals, and was not allowed to take an intermediate line of its own. Presumably it was thought that, in such conditions, the culprit’s own proposal would be a fairly reasonable one.

20^ Euripides made his Heracles denounce the whole mythology as an ‘unhappy fable of the minstrels’ on the tragic stage itself (H.F., 1346). Dr. Verral’s theory that the poet was running the risk of martyrdom by such declarations is quite unhistorical. Isocrates (xi. 38-40) makes an express point of attributing the misfortunes of the poets who related the stories (Homer, Stesichorus, Hesiod, Orpheus) to the righteous judgment of Heaven on their blasphemies. The person who first proposed to make false opinions in theology an offence against the State was Plato himself, in the tenth book of the Laws.

21^ At Apology, 31c, where Socrates himself has occasion to tell the story about the ‘sign,’ he remarks that it is ‘presumably what Meletus has caricatured in his indictment.’ But the very fact that the tale has to be told by Socrates, is of course, proof that Meletus had not spoken of it. This is just why the ‘caricature’ is said to have been made not in his speech but in the indictment. Socrates is humorously pretending, as Burnet says in loc., that he has only just discovered what was meant by the mysterious language of the accusation. The fanatic Euthyphron in Plato (Euthyphro 3b) suggests that the ‘sign’ may be what Meletus meant by calling Socrates a ‘maker of new gods,’ and Xenophon (who had, no doubt, read these dialogues) repeats the suggestion (Memorabilia I. i. 3), but only to point out that there was nothing in the facts about the ‘sign’ to sustain a charge of impiety.

22^ Cf. Aristophanes, Clouds 247, 252, 264, 367, 380, 627, alib.

23^ Memorabilia, I. ii. passim. The charges dealt with are teaching the young disrespect to their parents, criticizing such institutions of the democracy as the use of the lot in appointing to offices, educating Alcibiades and Critias, getting a bad sense out of lines from the poets. Since Socrates in Plato always treats the poets and their authority with irony, and since a good deal is made of this same charge in the Apology of Socrates by Libanius, the famous rhetorician of the fourth century A.D., which seems clearly based upon the pamphlet by Polycrates, it is likely that the point about the poets was urged at the trial as part of the case, and it may well be that Socrates had really said some of the things alleged against him about the dubious morality of the poets.

24^ Memorabilia, I. ii. 12: ‘The accuser said that two persons who had been familiars of Socrates had done more injury to the State than any one; Critias was the most rapacious and violent figure of the oligarchy, and Alcibiades the most unprincipled and licentious of the democracy.’ Xenophon’s reply is given at length, loc. cit., 13-16, 24-28.

25^ Apology 33a: ‘I have never made any iniquitous concession to any of those who are said by a misrepresentation to be my disciples, or to any one else. I have never been the teacher of any man whatsoever,’ etc. The persons meant by ‘those who are said to be my disciples’ are not Plato, and young men of his time. They had done no ill turns to the city for which any one could think of making Socrates responsible. We know from Plato himself (Epinomis vii. 325b) that it was only the condemnation of Socrates himself which led Plato to give up the project of entering politics as an adherent of the restored democracy.

26^ Isocrates, xi. 5: ‘You [Polycrates] gave him Alcibiades as a pupil, though no one had ever known of his being educated by him.’

27^ Aeschines, i. 173: ‘You put Socrates the sophist to death, because he was shown to have educated Critias.’

28^ We shall understand the situation better if we recall the obloquy heaped at the time of the recent War [1914-18] on a late philosophic statesman, mainly on account of an alleged sentence about his ‘spiritual home’ which appears never to have been uttered.

29^ The doubts once raised on the point by certain scholars in Germany are really only due to their assumption that the first object of an accused man must always be to ‘get off’ at any price. That may be true of most men, but it is not true of all, and least of all of a man like Socrates.

30^ This is Plato’s version (Apology 19a). Xenophon, in his own later-written Apology, is puzzled, as some Germans have been, by the fact that the Platonic speech, which he accepts as really reproducing the ‘lofty tone’ of Socrates, is not a judicious utterance for a man merely anxious to be acquitted, and therefore puts forward the ludicrous suggestion that Socrates deliberately provoked the Court to condemn him in order to ‘go off’ without suffering blindness and other infirmities of old age! (Xenophon, Apology 1-8.)

31^ We know from Plato (Apology 36a) that the majority for condemnation was 60. In Diogenes Laertius, ii. 41, it is said that Socrates was condemned by 281 votes more than those for acquittal. There must be some confusion here. It seems most probable (see Burnet’s note in loc.) that the total number of the jury was 500, and that 280 voted for condemnation, 220 for acquittal.

32^ To judge the adequacy of the offer, we have, of course, to take into account the high purchasing value of silver at the time. Apparently a mina was ordinarily thought a reasonable ransom for a prisoner of war. Thirty minae are frequently mentioned in the contemporary orators as a handsome dowry for a girl of middle-class family. We find Plato himself, a generation later, expecting to have to portion a niece with that sum (Epinomis 9 xiii. 361e). Xenophon (Apology 23) makes a distinct point of denying that Socrates made, or allowed his friends to make, any such proposal. This is an intentional contradiction of Plato, and deserves no credit. Plato was present at the scene; Xenophon was absent in Asia, and apparently does not see that the offer to pay a fine is not a confession of guilt.

33^ According to Diogenes Laertius (ii. 42), by 80 more votes than those given for the verdict. If this should be true, the voting would be 360 to 140 (not, as Burnet says, by an oversight on Apology, 38c, 300 to 200).

34^ In Plato (Apology 41b) Palamedes is mentioned as the typical example of the iniquitously condemned. It would have conflicted with Xenophon’s apologetic purpose to reproduce language in which Socrates professed a belief so uncommon among Athenians at large as that of the ‘life of the world to come.’ It is all the more significant that he has retained the reference to Palamedes (Xenophon, Apology 26) as a parallel to himself. This is no first-hand evidence that Socrates spoke thus, since Xenophon was far away at the time, but it shows that he had read Plato’s Apology and took it as a truthful narrative. His own version of the final speech is really Plato with the language about immortality suppressed. Similarly, at the end of the Cyropaedia (viii. 7, 17 ff.), where he has no apologetic purpose to consider, he puts into the mouth of the dying Cyrus a speech on immortality full of reminiscences of Plato’s Phaedo. It is a fair inference that he, like Plato, had inherited the belief from their common Master.

35^ Plato, Phaedo 115d. Imprisonment was not a penalty inflicted on citizens at Athens, except that debtors to the Treasury were commonly confined until they had paid their debt.

36^ That the delay was considerable is stated by Plato (Phaedo 58c); the more specific ‘one month’ comes from Xenophon (Memorabilia IV. viii. 2).

37^ Plato, Phaedo 60d ff. The alleged opening lines of both compositions are given by Diogenes Laertius (ii. 42).

38^ Plato never mentions the name of the poison employed, but we know from accounts of other executions that hemlock was commonly used. The description of the death of Socrates shows that the drug acted by a refrigeration, spreading upwards from the feet, and that death, accompanied by a spasm, ensued when the heart was affected. For a medical opinion to the effect that the agent used in this case was hemlock, see Burnet, Phaedo, Appendix I.

39^ Isocrates, xi. 5-6. Isocrates had, no doubt, read Plato’s Apology, but his language implies that he counted on a party among his readers who cherished the memory of Socrates. For the division of opinion about Alcibiades compare Isocrates, xvi, on the one side with Lysias, xiv, on the other.

Top ↑


What is the real significance of Socrates in the history of European thought? We may at once dismiss two views which have sometimes been held on this question as incapable of explaining the facts which need to be accounted for. Socrates was not a mere preacher of a commonplace morality of acting like an homme de bien for the utilitarian reason that bad ways ‘do not pay’ — a view of him suggested by undue attention to certain parts of Xenophon’s Memorabilia. Such a man would hardly have been put to death as a public danger; he would not have won the devotion of Plato, nor the general admiration of all the outstanding men of his age, or been caricatured as he was actually caricatured by Aristophanes. You may say Anytus misunderstood his man, Plato ‘idealized’ him, Aristophanes distorted his features. But there must have been something to prompt the misunderstanding, the idealization, the distortion. The subject of them must have been in some way an extraordinary, in fact a singular character, an ‘original,’ and we have to discover in what his singularity consisted. Nor can Socrates have been what he has sometimes been taken to be by superficial readers of Plato, a mere sceptic, quick at disturbing the convictions of others by ingenious questions, but without convictions, and intense convictions, of his own. Mere clever scepticism is as ephemeral in its results as it is temporarily dazzling; Socrates created the intellectual and moral tradition by which Europe has ever since lived. How this could be is what has to be explained.


“Socrates created the conception of the soul
which has ever since dominated European thinking.”


At bottom the answer seems to be a very simple one, and it may best be given in the elementary way in which it has been stated by Burnet.1 It was Socrates who, so far as can be seen, created the conception of the soul which has ever since dominated European thinking. For more than two thousand years it has been the standing assumption of the civilized European man that he has a soul, something which is the seat of his normal waking intelligence and moral character, and that, since this soul is either identical with himself or at any rate the most important thing about him, his supreme business in life is to make the most of it and do the best for it. There are, of course, a minority of persons who reject this theory of life, and some of them even deny the existence of a soul, but they are a small minority; to the vast mass of Europeans, to this day, the existence and the importance of the soul is a doctrine so familiar that it seems self-evident. The direct influence, indeed, which has done most to make the doctrine so familiar to ourselves is that of Christianity — but when Christianity came to the Graeco-Roman world it found the general conception of the soul which it needed already prepared for it by philosophy. Now the remarkable thing is that we find this conception of the soul as the seat of normal intelligence and character current in the literature of the generation immediately subsequent to the death of Socrates; it is common ground to Isocrates, Plato, and Xenophon, and thus cannot be the discovery of any one of them. But it is wholly, or all but wholly, absent from the literature of earlier times. It must thus have originated with some contemporary of Socrates, and we know of no contemporary thinker to whom it can be attributed other than Socrates himself, who is consistently made to teach it in the pages of both Plato and Xenophon.

Of course, we hear frequently enough in Greek literature, from Homer onward, of a thing which is called the psyche. But the important point is that there is perhaps no single passage in the earlier literature in which psyche means what soul has meant to us for so many centuries, the conscious personality which may be wise or foolish, virtuous or vicious, according to the ‘tendance’ and discipline it gets. In the earlier literature psyche regularly means one of two things, neither identical with what we have been taught to call the soul, according as the word is being used with associations derived from Homer or from Orphic religion.

In Homer the psyche means quite literally the ghost. It is something which is present in a man so long as he lives, and leaves him at death. It is, in fact, the ‘ghost’ which the dying man ‘gives up.’ But it is not the self; for Homer the ‘hero himself’ as distinguished from his psyche, is his body. Though a man cannot live when his psyche has left him, the psyche is never thought of as having anything to do with the ‘mental life,’ as we now call it; that is carried on, in Homer’s language, by the kear, heart, or the phrenes, midriff, both bodily organs. And the psyche which has left the body has no consciousness whatsoever, any more than a man’s shadow or his reflection in a pool; all that the departed psyche can do is to be seen from time to time in the dreams of the living. It is thus, at bottom, no more than the ‘breath’ which a man draws while he is alive and exhales finally when he ‘expires.’ Ionic science, in its account of the psyche, starts from these conceptions and carries the de-individualization of psyche still further. Its reigning view is that my psyche is simply that part of the ambient ‘air’ which I inhale. ‘Air’ is itself a ‘god,’ and so is conscious, and that is why I AM conscious just so long as I can continue to replenish my system with fresh portions of ‘the god.’ When I ‘breathe my last,’ the divine air in me simply goes back again to mingle with the common stock of the ‘air’ in the world at large; there is no real and permanent individual bearer of my ‘personality.’ (In the philosophy of Heraclitus, indeed, we can see that the ‘soul’ — which he supposed to be not ‘air’ but ‘fire’ — was very important, but it is a standing contradiction in his thinking that it at once has got to possess some sort of permanent individuality, in order to pass through the vicissitudes of birth, death, and re-birth, and yet is only a temporarily detached portion of the cosmic ‘fire.’)

In the Orphic religion, on the other hand, as in the kindred religion of the early Pythagoreans, the psyche is a more important thing. It has a permanent individuality, and is consequently immortal, and, in fact, a temporarily ‘fallen’ and exiled divinity. The great concern of the devotee is to practise rules of life, partly moral, partly ceremonial, which will lead to the final deliverance of the psyche from the ‘wheel of birth,’ and its restoration to its place among the gods. But it is not the soul, if by the soul we mean ‘that within us’ — to use the words of Socrates in Plato — ‘in virtue of which we are pronounced wise or foolish, good or bad.’ It is supposed by the Orphics to manifest its activity just when what we should call the ‘normal’ waking self is in abeyance — in dreams, visions, trances. As Pindar puts it, ‘[the psyche] sleeps while the members are active, but in men’s sleep it bodes forth in many a dream the impending issues of weal and woe.’ (Fr. 131, Bergk.) My intelligence and my character thus do not belong to the psyche in me, and its immortality, important as it is held by the Orphic to be, is not, properly speaking, my immortality. Where the psyche is spoken of, exceptionally, in earlier literature as the source of any actions in the everyday waking life, it is commonly mentioned in connection with the freakish appetites of which sober sense disapproves.2 It seems certain that at Athens in the fifth century the word psyche suggested to the ordinary man no more than ‘ghost’ does to us, and this is why Aristophanes in the Clouds talks about Socrates and his companions as σοφαὶ ψυχαί — he means to suggest that the life of these ‘thinkers’ is no better than that of so many ‘ghosts.’ So φιλοψυχία, concern for one’s psyche, meant the cowardly hanging on to ‘dear life’ which leads a man to ‘funk’ in the field.

Clearly, what is needed for the development of a ‘spiritual’ morality and religion is that the Orphic insistence on the supreme importance of ‘concern for the interests of the psyche’ shall be combined with the identification of this supremely precious psyche with the seat of normal personal intelligence and character. This is just the step which is taken in the doctrine of the soul taught by Socrates in both Plato and Xenophon, and it is by this breach with the Orphic tradition as much as by giving the conduct of life the central place which earlier thinkers had given to astronomy or biology that Socrates, in the hackneyed Ciceronian phrase, ‘brought philosophy down from heaven to earth.’ In other words, what he did was definitely to create philosophy as something distinct at once from natural science and from theosophy, or any amalgam of the two, and to effect this result once for all. The soul, as he conceives of it, has all the importance and the permanent individuality of the Orphic psyche. For reasons already given, it seems plain to me that we must believe Plato’s representations about his Master’s firm conviction of the soul’s immortality, and in the mouth of a Greek this means its essential divinity. This is the real justification of a mission to preach to all men, in season and out of season, the single duty of ‘tending the soul,’ and ‘making it as good as possible,’ whatever the cost to one’s fortunes or one’s body. But the identification of the soul which it is our first duty to ‘tend’ with the normal self means, of course, that the ‘tendance’ will not consist in the practice of ritual abstentions and purifications, but in the cultivation of rational thinking and rational conduct. A man’s duty will be to be able to ‘give account’ of, to have a rational justification for, what he believes and what he does. It is precisely by asserting and doing that for which we can give no rational justification that we display our indifference to the duty of ‘tending’ our souls. This is why when Socrates came to discharge his mission his first task was to convict the unenlightened of ‘ignorance,’ to show them how little intelligent justification they have for what they do or believe.

This Socratic doctrine of the soul, we must note, is neither psychology, in our sense of the word, nor psycho-physics. It tells us nothing on the question what the soul is, except that it is ‘that in us, whatever it is, in virtue of which we are denominated wise and foolish, good and evil,’ and that it cannot be seen or apprehended by any of the senses. It is no doctrine of the ‘faculties’ of the soul, any more than of its ‘substance.’ The thought is that the ‘work’ or ‘function’ of this divine constituent in man is just to know, to apprehend things as they really are, and consequently, in particular, to know good and evil, and to direct or govern a man’s acts so that they lead to a life in which evil is avoided and good achieved. What Socrates is concerned with is thus neither speculative nor empirical psychology,3 but a common principle of epistemology and ethics. To ‘make the soul as good as possible’ would be on the one side to attain the knowledge of existence as it really is, on the other to base one’s moral conduct on a true knowledge of ‘moral values.’ In both spheres the one thing to be overcome is the putting of ‘opinion,’ ‘fancy’ (doxa), assumptions which cannot be justified as true, in the place of knowledge. As science is ruined by the confusion of fancy with fact, so practical life is spoiled by a false estimate of good. We have now to see how this conception of knowledge of the truth as the one supreme business of the soul, and therefore of man, works out into the beginnings of a theory both of science and of moral conduct. We might be confident, even without the plain indications of Plato to guide us, that Socrates’ interest in the scientific problem belongs more particularly to the earlier part of his life, and that the ethical side of his thinking must have been almost exclusively dominant in the later years devoted to his mission to mankind. But we shall take the two things in the reverse order, in view of the much more general consensus of scholars on the characteristic features of the Socratic ethic.

I. Ethics. — When Aristotle has occasion to speak of the distinctive moral teaching of Socrates, he ascribes to him three special tenets, all at first sight paradoxical: (a) virtue, moral excellence, is identical with knowledge, and for that reason, all the commonly discriminated virtues are one thing; (b) vice, bad moral conduct, is therefore in all cases ignorance, intellectual error; (c) wrong-doing is therefore always involuntary, and there is really no such state of soul as that which Aristotle himself calls ‘moral weakness’ (acrasia), ‘knowing the good and yet doing the evil.’ Aristotle pretty clearly took these statements directly from his reading of one particular great dialogue of Plato, the Protagoras, where they are all to be found, but they fairly describe the substance of what Socrates has to say about morality in the dialogues of Plato’s earlier period, and they all reappear in a more commonplace form in the Memorabilia of Xenophon. We shall have the key to them if we can discover the point of view from which they cease to be paradoxes and begin to appear obvious.

We may most conveniently start with what appears to be the most violent paradox of all, the assertion that all wrong-doing is involuntary. ‘Moral weakness,’ the fact that men do what they themselves confess to be wrong, and that they do so without any forcing, is one of the most familiar facts of experience, and we are not to suppose that Socrates means to deny this. He means to say that the popular phrase we have just used gives an inadequate analysis of the fact. A man often enough does evil in spite of the fact that it is evil; no man ever does evil simply because he sees it to be evil, as a man may do good simply because he sees it to be good. A man has temporarily to sophisticate himself into regarding evil as good before he will choose to do it. As it is put in the Gorgias, there is one fundamental desire which is ineradicable in all of us: the desire for good or happiness. It is possible, in the case of all other objects, to prefer the appearance to the reality, the outward show, e.g. of power, or wealth, to the thing itself, but no one can wish for the show of good or happiness rather than the reality: this is the one case where the shadow cannot possibly be esteemed above the substance. To say that vice is involuntary means, therefore, that it never brings the vicious man that on which his heart, whether he knows it or not, like the heart of every one else, is really set. The typical Greek ‘monster of wickedness,’ the ‘tyrant’ who has raised himself above all the laws, may spend his whole life ‘doing as he pleases’ with the persons and property of all men, but just because he always does ‘just as he pleases,’ he never gets what he really wishes for. He wishes for felicity, and gets the extreme of infelicity, a hopelessly diseased soul. It would be better to be a criminal under sentence of death, because death may be just the sharp ‘surgery’ needed to cure the malady of the criminal’s soul. Thus, if a man really knew as assured and certain truth, of which he can no more doubt than he can doubt of his own existence, that the so-called ‘goods’ of body and ‘estate’ are as nothing in comparison with the good of the soul, and knew what the good of the soul is, nothing would ever tempt him to do evil. Evil-doing always rests upon a false estimate of goods. A man does the evil deed because he falsely expects to gain good by it, to get wealth, or power, or enjoyment, and does not reckon with the fact that the guilt of soul contracted immeasurably outweighs these supposed gains. Socrates thus agrees on one point with Hedonism, that wrong-doing is due to miscalculation; but the miscalculation is not one of ‘amounts of pleasure,’ but of values of good.4

We see now what is meant by saying that all the virtues are one thing, and that thing knowledge. The current view of mankind, in Socrates’ day as in ours, was that the moral virtues are a plurality; each is quite unlike the others, and you can have one in the highest degree without having any vestige of another — can, for example, be the brave des braves and yet as profligate as brave, or the most continent of men and yet the most grasping and unfair. Now Socrates admits that this is true, if by the virtues you mean what he calls in Plato ‘vulgar virtue,’ the sort of outward respect paid to an accepted code of conduct by men who have no personal conviction of the supreme importance of the soul, and the identity of true happiness with its ‘health,’ and merely conduct themselves decently because the habits of their society require it of them, and they expect to be made uncomfortable if they behave otherwise. But this ‘vulgar’ virtue is a mere illusory counterfeit of the true. True virtue is an affair of intense conviction, personal knowledge of the true moral ‘values.’ There is thus one single principle behind all its various manifestations in the varied situations of life. A man who has grasped this principle with the assured insight of knowledge cannot, then, apply it in some situations and not in others. Real knowledge of what is good for the soul will display itself in a right attitude to all the situations of life, and thus in the ‘philosopher’s’ life the apparent dividing lines between one type of moral excellence and another will vanish. The whole of his conduct will be the exhibition of one excellence, steady and assured certainty of the true ‘scale of good.’ This explains the curious fact that more than one of the Platonic dialogues ends in a singular, apparently negative result. We are invited to consider what is the true character of some currently recognized virtue (temperance in the Charmides, courage in the Laches). Reflection seems to be leading us up to the conclusion that the quality under discussion is really knowledge of good, when we are brought to a pause by the observation that this appears to be the definition not of the particular virtue ostensibly under discussion, but of. all virtue as a single whole. Formally this is treated as a proof that we are still as ignorant of the answer to the question propounded to us as we were at the outset. In fact, we are to understand, the attempt to define one virtue ends in something which is no more a definition of that virtue than of another, for the reason that in principle all virtue is one.

Of course, the knowledge with which Socrates thus identifies virtue is not anything and everything to which the name knowledge can be given; it is definitely knowledge of what is nowadays called ‘moral value,’ knowing what is my good. Now this leads to a real difficulty: how is such knowledge to be come by? On the one hand, if virtue is knowledge, the having or not having it is no matter of simple congenital endowment; men no more come into the world born good than they come into the world already born in possession of any other kind of knowledge; they have to win their knowledge. Yet the popularly current view that we automatically pick up ‘goodness,’ as we pick up the use of our mother-tongue, under the influence of good parents and a good social environment cannot be true. It is notorious that Pericles and the other outstanding men whom the Athenian public regards as eminently its ‘best men’ have been quite unable to impart their own excellences to their sons; the sons have commonly been quite inferior persons. On the other hand, the eminent ‘sophists’ profess to be able to ‘teach goodness,’ as they might teach some technical accomplishment, by a course of instruction. Now, if goodness is knowledge and nothing but knowledge, it certainly must be capable of being taught somehow; the man who has this knowledge must be able to direct another to the acquisition of it. And yet the sophistic profession of being able to teach it by a course of lectures must be hollow. The point which Socrates is represented by Plato as urging repeatedly against the sophists and their admirers is a simple one. What the sophist can teach is at best a professional speciality of some kind, how to do something which men in general cannot do. But virtue, or goodness, is no speciality with its restricted domain; its sphere is the whole domain of human conduct. And a specialism is, again, something which may be put to a good use or to an ill one, just as medical knowledge may be used to cure, but may equally be used to kill.5 At best the sophist can impart the specialist knowledge; what he cannot impart is the ‘knowledge of good’ which will ensure that the use made of it shall be good and not evil.

How, then, does a man learn the one kind of knowledge which it steads him most to have, knowledge of good? It is not clear that Socrates had ever reached a final solution of the problem. But we can perhaps discover the general character of the answer he would have given. According to Plato,6 he had been struck by the Orphic doctrine that there are means by which the soul can be restored to remembrance of her forgotten divine origin, and from this hint he had developed the conviction that the acquisition of knowledge generally is in reality a process of ‘recollection’ or ‘recognition’ (anamnesis) in which particular sensible facts prompt or suggest the assertion of a universal principle which transcends the facts themselves. By drawing a diagram and asking a series of pertinent questions, the mathematician leads a pupil to recognize a universal proposition. He need impart no information; if the right diagram is drawn, and the mind of the pupil set at work on it by the right questions, it will produce the right conclusion from within, by its own action, as though from a store of truth which it already possesses unconsciously. The truth so ‘learned’ is reached by a personal ‘discovery,’ to which the ‘learner’ has simply been stimulated by his ‘teacher,’ and yet is also ‘recognized’ as already implied in what the ‘learner’ had all along known. In the same way, the acute interrogations of a Socrates who compels us to ‘give account’ of our conduct of our lives, prompt the mind of the interrogated to ‘recognition’ of the implications of the moral standards by which we estimate our own conduct and our neighbour’s. This is the starting-point from which Plato was to develop his own theory of ‘philosophy’ as created by the friction of minds employed in the joint pursuit after truth.

The Greek mind rightly made no distinction between the principles of private and those of public conduct, morals and ‘polities’; and Socrates consistently applied his conviction of the identity of ‘goodness’ with a right estimate of ‘values’ to the morality of the State and its statesmen. The worth of a State, and of its public men, depended, in his eyes, wholly on the degree to which the national life was based on a true scale of good. It was out of the question that, with all his practical loyalty to the constitution, he should approve of the principle of democracy, the sovereignty of the multitude who have no knowledge of the good, and have never even dreamed that such knowledge is the necessary qualification for the direction of their affairs. The judgments on the Athenian democracy of the fifth century put into his mouth in Plato’s Gorgias and Republic are much harder than anything Plato has to say of democratic government on his own account in such later dialogues as the Politicus and the Laws, and it seems to me probable that the severity of these verdicts comes from Socrates rather than from Plato.7 The very principle of democracy, if it can be called a principle, according to the Republic, is the refusal to require any superiority of intellect or character as a qualification for leadership; in the democratic community, as Nietzsche puts it, there is ‘one flock and no shepherd,’ and this is why its normal fate is to fall into the hands of an able and unscrupulous ‘dictator’ (or, as the Greeks called him, ‘tyrant’). Equally severe is the condemnation pronounced by the Gorgias on all the famous leaders of the Athenian democracy, from Themistocles to Pericles, with the one exception, in part, of the ‘just’ Aristides. None of them all had the knowledge of good which is the one thing needful in life, as we see from two considerations. None of them — not even Aristides — could impart any goodness he possessed to his own son, and none, except perhaps Aristides, made the public ‘soul’ better by his tendance of it. Themistocles and Pericles and the others made Athens powerful and wealthy, but they did nothing for the moral of the people; they ‘filled the city with ships and docks, not with righteousness’; gave it worldly prosperity, but no true moral ideals. Hence we are told in the Gorgias that though they may have been efficient ‘body-servants’ of the public, they have no claim to be, as true statesmen must be, its ‘physicians.’ It is clear that Socrates really habitually used the kind of arguments Plato ascribes to him about the incapacity of the Athenian public men to impart ‘goodness’ to their sons as a proof that their own apparent ‘goodness’ was not the genuine thing. In the Meno Anytus is introduced expressly to warn him that this depreciation of the national heroes is a dangerous sport — a plain indication of Plato’s belief that it had much to do with provoking the attack which ended in his prosecution.

From the Socratic point of view, the proper organization of society would be one in which every man’s social status and function, as statesman, soldier, or producer, is determined by the nature of the work his aptitudes, understanding, and character fit him to discharge. This is precisely the ideal which is embodied in outline in the account of the ideal city which fills the earlier books of Plato’s Republic. So far, the scheme may truly be said to be directly of Socratic inspiration. How far any of its details are actually of Socratic origin is another question, though it is suggestive that this seems to be so with one of its most original features, the proposal to admit women on the same terms as men to public employment, military and civil, and the education which qualifies for it. That Socrates actually entertained an ideal of this kind seems to be shown by the fact that Aeschines also in his dialogue Aspasia dwelt on the political capacity of Aspasia herself and others, and the military ability believed to have been shown by the real or legendary Persian princess Rhodogyne. Xenophon also incidentally puts into the mouth of his Socrates the thesis that, with the necessary training, a woman is capable of the same things as a man.8c

II. Theory of Knowledge and Scientific Method. — Aristotle remarks in the Metaphysics that ‘two things must in justice be ascribed to Socrates, inductive arguments and universal definition.9 This does not take us very far; Aristotle is clearly intending less to give us a complete characterization of Socrates than to specify certain constituents of his own philosophy as derived from him, and he seems to be basing his statement simply on his reading of Plato’s dialogues, which illustrate the point abundantly. Xenophon’s apologetic interest in the soundness of his old teacher’s moral lessons leaves him little inclination to talk about anything else. Our chances of being able to discover something more about Socrates as a thinker on other than strictly ethical topics stand or fall with the historical truth of the autobiographical narrative put into his mouth in Plato’s Phaedo.10 Now it seems to me, as I have already said, that we are bound to take this narrative as being substantially what Plato regarded as historical fact. The alternative is to suppose that an account of what Socrates said of himself on the last day of his life, in the presence of a number of intimate friends who were all living when that account was published, and certain to read it, is a fiction which all these readers would immediately detect. No one is really courageous enough to be thorough with such a theory. Everybody, for instance, accepts as fact the story of the introduction of Socrates to the book of Anaxagoras, and his disappointment with it, though we have no evidence for the fact beyond the statement of the Phaedo. But that statement in the Phaedo is merely the beginning of a coherent narrative, and it is therefore incumbent on us in consistency either to accept the rest of the narrative as substantially accurate, or to treat the initial statement with the same scepticism as all that follows it. I have little doubt for myself which is the more reasonable course. No sane man, of course, would deny that Plato, like every great artist, mixed his own mind with his object. It is quite another matter to assert that he consciously presents us with his own features in a pretended portrait of Socrates.11

According to the Phaedo, then, the immediate effect on Socrates of his discovery that Anaxagoras dogmatized about Nature in the same arbitrary fashion as his precursors was to lead him to strike out a new method in the search for truth. If we cannot discover the truth about things by direct inspection of the things themselves, we may attempt to reach it by examining the statements, or theories (logoi), which we make about them. The apparent indirectness of the procedure is Socrates’ reason for humorously proceeding to depreciate it as the ‘make-shift of an amateur.’ Really, of course, he holds that it affords us our one and only chance of getting any genuine knowledge. The procedure he is describing is precisely that which, as we see from Xenophon,12 as well as from Plato, he called dialectic, a name which properly means the method of ‘conversation.’ The thought which explains the use of the name is that truth has to be reached by dint of dialogue, or debate, which may be carried on between two inquirers, or also within the heart of a single inquirer, as his ‘soul’ questions itself and answers its own questions. The truth, which is not to be discovered by any direct inspection of ‘facts,’ may be beaten out in the critical confrontation of rival interpretations of them. It comes, when it comes, as the conclusion to a debate.

It is this method of confrontation of rival ‘arguments’ or ‘theories’ which Aristophanes wittily and wickedly burlesques in the Clouds. Protagoras also had said, in a very different sense, that ‘there are two arguments about everything,’ two sides to every case, and that the art of effective advocacy which he taught aims at making the ‘weaker case’ — that which unskilfully presented would have got the worse with the audience — the ‘stronger.’ Aristophanes puts on this harmless dictum the sense that the object of advocacy is to make the morally worse case appear the better, and then transfers the procedure to Socrates, with the result that the rival ‘arguments’ are brought on the stage as Virtue and Vice, and Vice, of course, drives Virtue out of the field. This is pure burlesque, but it pre-supposes as its foundation the fact that, in the infancy of Plato, Socrates was already known as specially interested in the confrontation of ‘arguments’ of some kind.

The Phaedo gives us a fairly full account of the nature of the procedure. The method is that Socrates starts from some proposition which, on any grounds, commends itself to him as presumably true. This he calls his initial hypothesis, and he proceeds to ask himself ‘what must follow if this is admitted,’ that is, to deduce its consequences. The truth of the initial hypothesis being at present unquestioned, whatever follows from it is also set down as true, and whatever conflicts with it as false. Thus the assumption of the method is simply that truth is a coherent system, and that nothing which conflicts with a true principle can be true. We must note, of course, that the assumed principle which Socrates calls his hypothesis is not taken to be hypothetical in the sense of being a ‘pure supposal.’ Socrates takes it as the starting-point of an argument because he presumes it to be true, or because it is common ground to himself and the other party to the discussion. On the other hand, there is no question of asserting it as a self-evident and final truth. It may be called in question, and in that case requires to be defended by being deduced as a consequence from some more ultimate and less disputable hypothesis. The important rule of method is that the question what consequences follow from the hypothesis, and the question whether the hypothesis itself is true, must be kept distinct. So long as we are still concerned with the former question, that of the consequences, the hypothesis itself must be left unquestioned.

So far, the method ascribed to Socrates in the Phaedo is clearly in principle that which has proved itself the one path to truth in scientific theory down to our own time. The contrast drawn between the direct procedure of the Ionian physicists, which had led nowhere, and the method of studying things in the ‘statements’ we make about them is precisely that also drawn by De Morgan between the erroneous method of Bacon, who assumes that facts are there to draw a theory from, and the sound method of Newton, who treats the facts as there to test theory by.13 The one notable difference is that Socrates makes no special reference to the verification of theory by the confrontation of theoretical consequences with observational fact. Verification, however, finds its proper place in the elaboration of the Socratic thought by Plato and his Academy, whose technical name for a scientific theory which clearly accounts for all the relevant observed facts was an hypothesis which ‘saves appearances.’ (The ‘appearances’ are the facts as observed; to ‘save’ them is to account for them all in a coherent way.) Of course, neither Socrates nor Plato could have contemplated the modern extension of verification by experiments devised expressly for the purpose.

So far there is some independent evidence that the statements of the Phaedo about the method of Socrates are historical. Xenophon was aware that his practice, when one of his theses was disputed, was to ‘bring the whole discussion back to the hypothesis,’ that is, the initial position which was common ground to himself and his opponent (Memorabilia IV. vi. 13), though this, of course, may only mean that Xenophon had read the Phaedo and seen no reason to distrust its statements. It is more significant to my mind that Plato himself apparently makes Protagoras refer, without any further explanation, to the method of taking some proposition as an hypothesis which is not to be questioned so long as we are concerned with discovering its consequences, as something distinctively characteristic of Socrates, in a dialogue feigned to have been held before Plato’s own birth.14 We can see, moreover, from what quarter Socrates is likely to have derived the suggestion of the method. Rigorous deduction of the consequences of an hypothesis was the peculiar method of the famous Zeno of Elea, though it was the hypotheses of his opponents which he treated in this way, and his object was to discredit them by showing that they led to impossible consequences, as he is made to explain himself to the youthful Socrates in Plato’s Parmenides (128c-e).

As far as this many, if not most, careful students of the evidence would probably be willing to follow us. Most of them may decline to take the further step of accepting as fundamentally true to fact what the narrative of the Phaedo goes on to say about the nature of the particular hypothesis adopted by Socrates himself as the basis of his thinking. This, it is said, is nothing but the famous ‘Theory of Ideas,’ and it is commonly assumed without proof, or with no proof but a few ambiguous expressions in Aristotle, that this doctrine was discovered by Plato for the first time after the death of Socrates. For my own part, I feel with Burnet that it is inconceivable that any thinker should introduce an eminently original discovery of his own to the world by representing it as something which had long been familiar to a number of living contemporaries who were certain to read his work and detect any misrepresentation. I hold, therefore, that we must accept the statements of the Phaedo as substantially true to fact, and have to explain the evidence of Aristotle, if we accept it at all for more than his own private conjecture, in a way which will not conflict with Plato. We must remember, of course, that Plato has mixed his own personality with his object in the very act of depicting it, but we must take this to be done inevitably and without conscious distortion of truth.

The problem which had perplexed Socrates was that of the ‘cause of coming-to-be and ceasing-to-be.’ Why does a thing make its appearance in the world or disappear from it? Why does a thing come to exhibit a quality which it had not before, or to lose one which it had? The physicists had their answer to this question; they found the causes of these changes in physical agents, which they assigned variously and arbitrarily. Reflection on the implications of the thesis of Anaxagoras about Mind as the source of the order in the world suggested to Socrates that these physical agents, whatever they may be, are at best only concomitant causes, or indispensable conditions, of an event; the real cause is, in every case, that it is best that things should be as they are, and in a mind-ordered world everything will be disposed as it is best that it should be. In this way, Socrates introduced into philosophy that ‘teleological’ or ‘finalist’ conception of the order of the universe as realizing an end of absolute value which was to be fully worked out and transmitted to later times as the chief heritage of Greek philosophical thought by Plato, Aristotle, and Plotinus.

The abandonment of the old naïf method of trying to discover truth by a simple inspection of ‘facts’ meant, of course, that Socrates could not dream of learning by direct inspection what the particular details of the world-order are, and why it is best that they should be as they are. But his conviction that there is an intelligible order in everything, and that it is a wise order, gave him a characteristic point of view from which to approach the question why a thing comes to be or ceases to be, acquires or loses a character. He speaks of this attitude in the Phaedo as nothing novel to his auditors, but one of which they have repeatedly heard from him. If a thing becomes what if was not before, if, for example, it becomes beautiful, this is always for one and the same reason, that Beauty has ‘become present to’ the thing; if it ceases to be beautiful, Beauty has ‘withdrawn’ from it. Or, in an alternative phrase, a thing which is beautiful is so just because, and so long as, it ‘partakes’ of Beauty; a figure is triangular just so long as, and because it ‘partakes of the triangle; and so forth. Beauty, or, as the Greek language expresses it, ’the Beautiful,’ ’the triangle,’ and the like, are what in this doctrine are called Forms or Patterns (eidē, ideai),15 and a thing is what it is, has the characters it has, because it ‘partakes’ of the Forms of which it does ‘partake.’ And there are the following important points to be noted about these Forms, (1) The ‘things which partake of a Form’ are all perishable; they begin to be and cease to be, but the Form, Beauty, the Triangle, etc., neither begins to be, nor ceases to be; it is strictly what Dr. Whitehead calls an ’eternal object.’ (2) The things which we perceive by our senses only ‘partake of,’ or ‘resemble,’ the Forms imperfectly. We never see a stick which is flawlessly straight, or a patch which is exactly and perfectly triangular, and we never perhaps meet with an act of perfect justice; we only see approximately straight sticks and approximately triangular patches, and come across acts of approximate justice. But ‘the straight line’ or ‘the triangle’ about which the geometer tells us is perfectly straight or triangular, and the justice of which the moralist talks as a duty is perfect justice. (3) The things which ‘partake of the Form’ may be indefinitely many; the Form itself is strictly one. Even in geometry, where we talk of many triangles which are all assumed to be perfectly triangular, what the geometer is interested in proving is not the properties of this triangle or that triangle, but those of ‘the’ triangle.16 And it is always the Form, never this or that thing which ‘partakes of a Form, which is the object of which we are talking in science. I know as a scientific truth that any two sides of the triangle must be greater together than the third side; I do not know that two sides of this patch before me must be greater than the third, since I do not know that this visible patch really is triangular.

We should like, of course, if we could, to know something more of these Forms. Of what things are there Forms (and, consequently, of what things can we have scientific knowledge)? And, again, do the Forms constitute a system of any kind? We can see from the polemical allusions of Aristotle that at a later date Plato’s Academy had answers, not always concordant answers, to these questions, and that Aristotle found all these answers unsatisfactory. But we are not entitled to read back into the Phaedo developments which belong to Plato’s old age, and we may even doubt whether in the Republic Plato may not be unconsciously ‘colouring’ his picture of Socrates more than he knows as his argument advances. From the examples given in the Phaedo itself it would seem that what Socrates was chiefly thinking of is, on the one side, the objects of which the mathematician can give us perfect and absolute definitions in geometry and arithmetic, and on the other the ideal standards and norms of the moralist (the number 3, the triangle, the Just, and the like). And this impression is borne out for us by a dialogue written by Plato at a late period in his career, the Parmenides, in which Socrates is expounding his theory to the great Eleatic philosophers Parmenides and Zeno, and defending it, not very satisfactorily, against their criticism. He is made there to say (Parmenides 129-130) that he feels quite sure that there are Forms of such things as Like and Unlike, Unity, Multitude, Just, Good, but very doubtful whether there are Forms of Man, Fire, Water, and still more doubtful about Hair, Mud, Dirt. In fact, he is sure of his ground in Mathematics and Morals, but very unsure of it everywhere else. We may infer that the first impulse to the formation of the theory came from reflection on mathematical and moral truth. This is what we should expect if the doctrine originated with Socrates, and if Socrates were the man Plato depicts. The very terminology used seems to come in the first instance from Pythagorean mathematics. There is clear evidence that the word eidos was the old Pythagorean name for ‘figure,’ a sense of the word which persists in some stereotyped phrases in Euclid and other third-century geometers, though their common word for figure is a different one (schema).17 And Plato frequently represents Socrates as deeply impressed by the need for moral standards by which controversies about right and wrong may be determined, as disputes about area or volume are settled by an appeal to geometry, or disagreements about weight by resort to the balance.

We see that the doctrine is a first attempt to do justice to the a priori factor in knowledge, the universality and necessity of scientific truths most conspicuously evident in the propositions of pure mathematics and pure ethics, and that those disciplines are taken as the model of what all science should be. We understand thus why the Forms have been identified by later philosophers with ‘universals,’ ‘concepts,’ ‘class-notions.’ But to speak of them so involves a really unhistorical transposition of a simpler thought. It is to make Socrates talk like Aristotle, or Kant, and this cannot be done without risk of misunderstanding, though his doctrine is the ultimate source of theirs. If we would avoid all such misunderstandings, it is best to say simply that the Form is that — whatever it may be — which we mean to denote whenever we use a significant ‘common name’ as the subject of a strictly and absolutely true proposition, the object about which such a proposition makes a true assertion. Such objects, not the sensible things disclosed in bodily perception, are, according to Socrates, the most real things there are, and the only things which are fully real. The soul, as we saw, has one single fundamental activity, that of knowing realities as they really are, and it is only in knowing the Forms that this activity is successfully discharged. Where the mind is not face to face with a Form, we have only opinion or belief, a belief which may, of course, in many cases be quite sufficient for the needs of everyday life, but we have not knowledge; the element of ’necessary connection’ is missing.

Do the Forms, which are the proper objects of genuine knowledge, form an organized whole or system? They should do so, no doubt, since, according to the Phaedo, the whole doctrine of them as the explanation of ‘coming-into-being and ceasing-to-be’ is inspired by the still more ultimate conviction that in a mind-permeated world all things are ordered as it is best they should be, and the Good — itself a Form — is therefore the cause of the whole order. This is strictly in accord with a famous passage of the Republic (506d-509b), where Socrates speaks of the Good, or Form of good, as holding the same supreme and central position in the realm of Forms apprehended by the intellect which its ‘offspring’ the Sun holds in the visible world. As the sun in the visible world is the source at once of the life of the things we see and the light by which they are seen, so the good in the world disclosed to thought is the source at once of the reality of the Forms we apprehend and of the knowledge by which they are apprehended. And as the sun, though the source of light and growth, is not the same thing as either, so the good is neither ‘being’ nor ‘knowledge,’ but something which is the transcendent source of both. But Socrates is made to confess that as it is the supreme feat of corporeal vision to be able to look on the sun, so it is the supreme and most difficult achievement of the mind to know the Good. He himself, in this passage, confesses his own inability to speak of it in any language but that of parable and metaphor. Plato has been commonly thought in this passage to be talking of a personal speculation of his own of which the Master whose voice he is borrowing had never dreamed. In view of the intimate connection made in the ‘autobiographical’ pages of the Phaedo between the hypothesis of Forms and the conviction that the Good is the universal cause, I find it difficult to subscribe to this opinion. I should rather judge that the language and imagery of this splendid passage are those of Plato in his ‘golden prime,’ but the thought is one directly necessitated by the meditations born of the first falling-in with the book of Anaxagoras.

It is clear that the doctrine of Forms, in the shape in which, as I hold, we must be prepared to ascribe it to Socrates, creates difficulties as well as removes them. In particular, it leaves wholly unexplained the relation of the Form to sensible fact which it calls its ‘presence,’ or its being ‘participated in.’ Is what we call a sensible thing merely a temporary assemblage of Forms, or ‘universals,’ and if it is more, what else is it? No one has pointed out these difficulties more incisively than Plato himself in his dialogue Parmenides, and it seems at least plain that the final form of Plato’s own teaching, which we have to reconstruct imperfectly from the puzzling hints of Aristotle, was an attempt to find an answer to the problem. Aristotle himself was so perplexed by the results that he comes to treat the whole doctrine of Forms itself as a mistaken attempt to separate the ‘universal characters’ of individual sensible things from the things themselves, and then to set up these ‘abstractions’ as a second set of super-sensible things which somehow produce the things we see and handle. It is, he says, as though a man who had to count a number of articles were to fancy that he must begin by doubling it. He believed himself to have got rid once for all of an unreal and insoluble problem by his own formula that the ‘form’ only exists in the individual sensible thing, and is just its ‘essential character.’ Yet the problem is still with us, in spite of Aristotle, as a very real crux in the latest attempts to furnish a philosophy of the sciences. We still find ourselves asking what is the ‘status’ of ‘scientific objects.’ Just what are the things of which the mathematician and the physicist discourse? Or again, what is a moral ‘ideal’? And what is the relation of the ‘scientific object’ to the things we touch or see, and how, again, are ‘value’ and ‘fact’ related? Natural and moral philosophy are still far from having answered these questions with finality, and even further from having escaped the necessity of asking them. The unique greatness of Socrates lies in the fact that he was the first man in the world to raise them with the clear understanding of what he was doing.


Several of the companions of Socrates were active after his death as heads of philosophical schools, and one, Antisthenes, was a voluminous writer. It has been common to speak of these men and their followers as ‘minor Socratics.’ It is, to my mind, very doubtful how far this language, which reflects the artificial schematism of Alexandrian biography, is justified. The Megarian opponents of Aristotle in the fourth century, their contemporaries, Diogenes and the other eccentrics popularly nicknamed Cynics, the Hedonist moralists of Cyrene in the third, were affiliated to Socrates through Euclides, Antisthenes, and Aristippus respectively. But there is no evidence of the existence of any Cyrenaic school before the days of the successors of Alexander; the Megarics, who showed themselves pugnacious opponents of Aristotle, clearly held views not to be reconciled with the strict Monism ascribed by all our authorities to Euclides; though Diogenes and his imitators professed a great reverence for Antisthenes, it is not clear that they regarded themselves as in any way related to him as a ‘founder.’ And Euclides, Aristippus, Antisthenes, were all rather admiring friends than ‘disciples’ of Socrates. The doctrines of Euclides were a direct inheritance from the Eleatics; Aristippus is expressly recorded to have had no doctrines at all; the paradoxical views for which Antisthenes is chiefly remembered, his denial of the possibility of contradiction, and the like, come not from Socrates, but from the ‘sophists.’ For all purposes of importance, Socrates had just one ‘successor’ — Plato.


Endnotes

1^ See, in particular, Burnet’s essay, ‘The Socratic Conception of the Soul’ (Proceedings of the British Academy, viii. 235-260), and his article, ‘Socrates,’ in Hastings’ Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics, xi.

2^ As when the Cyclops in Euripides says he will for once ‘do his psyche a good turn’ by a cannibal debauch (Cyclops, 340). So the Romans said genio indulgere in the same sense, and anima causa agere, ‘to act on one’s whim.’

3^ Empirical psychology, founded by Alcmaeon of Crotona, is represented, in the age of Socrates, by those scientific Pythagoreans who taught that the soul is the ‘attunement of’ the melody given out by the body, a doctrine, as is shown in the Phaedo, quite inconsistent with the religion of both Pythagoras and Socrates.

4^ This is the real point of the argument in Plato’s Protagoras, where Socrates appears at first sight to be talking Hedonism. He wants to prove to the ‘many’ that, even on their own theory that good and pleasure are the same thing, it is not a paradox to identify the courage of the virtuous man with knowledge, since they will admit that the coward who runs away from danger is making a false computation of the ‘balance of pleasures and pains.’

5^ t is notorious that the clever poisoner in our criminal annals is commonly a medical man.

6^ See particularly Meno 81a-85e, where the theory is elaborately illustrated by a ‘lesson’ in geometry given by Socrates to a slave-boy ignorant of the science, and Phaedo, 72e ff., where there is a similar reference to the acquisition of geometrical knowledge. In both places the doctrine is brought into connection with the immortality of the soul, but it is made clear that, as a theory of what the discovery of a truth is, it is independent of this religious tenet. (It reappears, in fact, at the end of Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics ii, without any religious associations, as Aristotle’s own account of the way in which first principles are suggested by ‘induction.’) In the Phaedo (loc. cit.) the doctrine that ‘learning is just recognition’ is expressly said by Simmias, speaking to Socrates, to be ‘the doctrine you are so constantly repeating.’ Unless we are willing to regard the Phaedo as a gigantic and unpardonable mystification, this seems to me proof that the theory really belongs to Socrates. For a brief statement of Plato’s own allied convictions see Epinomis, vii. 341c, and the comments of Burnet on the passage (Greek Philosophy, Pt. 1, pp. 221-222).

7^ When the language of the earlier dialogues is taken as expressing Plato’s personal opinions, the more favourable judgments of the later dialogues are explained as due to the mellowing influence of time on a mind lacerated by the fate of Socrates. It may be so, but there is also always the psychological possibility that the harsher verdicts are those of Socrates himself. His disillusionment as the temper of the Athenian democracy grew narrower and harder in the course of the great war would be all the bitterer that he had grown up in the great ‘fifty years’ before the war, and presumably had hoped and expected very different things. In a very late dialogue, the Timaeus, Plato makes Socrates confess to being something of a doctrinaire in politics, owing to his lack of personal experience of public life (Timaeus 19d). We learn from Xenophon (Memorabilia 1. ii. 9) that sarcasms about the democratic practice of filling magistracies by sortition was one count in the case against Socrates to which he is replying.

8^ See the fragments of the Aspasia in the editions of Krauss and Dittmar. Xenophon’s testimony to Socrates’ belief that ‘a woman is no worse endowed by nature than a man, though not his equal in judgment or physical strength,’ will be found at Symposium ii. 9. For evidence from Xenophon to the demand of knowledge as the one qualification for sovereignty, see Memorabilia III. ix. 10, and compare the whole of III. vi. where Socrates dissuades Glaucon from a premature entrance on public life by exposing his ignorance of military and financial statistics. That Xenophon speaks only of such ignorance of facts, not of the graver ignorance of ‘moral values,’ strikes me as characteristic of the man.

9^ Metaphysics 1078b 27. Some good recent German students make a point of denying that Socrates was really interested in ‘definition.’ This is true in the sense that his concern was not with theoretical labels for their own sake, but with a practical rule of conduct. What justifies Aristotle’s way of expressing himself is that he is thinking of the formal structure of such works as Charmides, Laches, Protagoras, Meno, Republic IV.

10^ Phaedo 96a-100c. The whole passage should be studied carefully with the annotations to it in Burnet’s edition of the dialogue (Oxford, 1911).

11^ A great portrait-painter always puts his own personality into his portraits. If he were an inferior artist, the portrait would be different. But he does not give his sitters his own nose or eyebrows.

12^ A chapter of some length in the Memorabilia (IV. vi.) is devoted to illustrations of the way in which Socrates made those who associated with him ‘more dialectical.’ He did this, according to Xenophon, by urging them to think precisely and to express their thought intelligibly.

13^ A. De Morgan, A Budget of Paradoxes (ed. 2), i. 88.

14^ Protagoras 351e. The name hypothesis is not used here, but Protagoras proposes to Socrates to discuss the thesis that the good is pleasure ‘in your regular way,’ by working out its consequences.

15^ But it is misleading to call them, as they have so long been called, Ideas. That suggests to us that they are some one’s thoughts, ‘ideas in some one’s head,’ precisely what the theory does not mean.

16^ We see this in an interesting way from the language, e.g., of Analytical Geometry about ’the equation to the circle,’ or of Arithmetic about ’the number six.’

17^ The same sense of ‘patterns’ accounts for our language about figures of speech, and figures of the syllogism.

Top ↑


Bibliographical Note

It would be impossible to furnish a work like the present with a complete conspectus of the enormous mass of literature — good and bad — connected with the subject of Socrates and his significance. I must content myself with mentioning a very few recent works which, in my opinion, an English reader will find useful or stimulating.

Burnet, J. Greek Philosophy, Part One, Thales to Plato. (Oxford, 1914.)

Burnet, J. The Socratic Doctrine of the Soul,
  in Proceedings of the British Academy for
  1915-1916, pp. 235 ff.

Burnet, J. Article ‘Socrates,’ in Hastings’
  Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics, vol. xi.

Burnet, J. The Phaedo of Plato. (Oxford, 1911.)

Burnet, J. The Euthyphro, Apology and Crito of Plato. (Oxford, 1924.)

Taylor, A. E. Plato’s Biography of Socrates,
  in Proceedings of the British Academy for
  1917-1918, pp. 93 ff.

Robin, L. Editions of the Phaedo and Symposium of Plato,
  in the Collection des Universités de France.

Ritter, C. Sokrates. Tübingen, 1931.

Bruns, I. Das literarische Porträt der Griechen (1896).

Adam, J. Editions of the Apology (1905), Crito (1891),
  Euthyphro (1890), and Protagoras (1893) of Plato.
  (Cambridge University Press.)

For the historical background of the life of Socrates I would refer the reader acquainted with German primarily to vols. iv and v of E. Meyer’s Geschichte des Altertums, though the older narrative by Grote still retains most of its value.

I have made little reference to the nineteenth-century literature, as I hold that, with all its merits, most of it pursued a false line in distrusting the narrative of Plato. But I would specially commend for its scholarship and sanity out of this vast literature the work of Grote, Plato and the other Companions of Socrates. The Alexandrian version of the life of Socrates is most readily accessible to the English reader in the text and translation of Diogenes Laertius by R. D. Hicks (Loeb Classical Library, Heinemann, 1925), where it occupies pp. 148-177 of vol. i. It may be worth while to mention two sane and instructive works dealing with the ‘erotic’ side of Socrates as depicted by Plato: R. Lagerborg, Die platonische Liebe, Leipzig, 1926, and the briefer essay of C. Ritter, Platonische Liebe, Tübingen, 1931. I would particularly commend the former and larger book.

Much that is of value will be found in the large works of C. Ritter and U. von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, both entitled Platon, but Socrates is, of course, only incidentally the subject of these. A good conspectus of recent theories about the worth of the various authorities will be found in A. Diès, Autour de Platon, Paris, 1927, vol. i. pp. 127-243.

Top ↑




Socrates of Athens
470 B.C. – 399 B.C.
The father of hypothesis and elenchus,
the Socratic method; the anti-politician
who challenged men’s premisses


Socrates


References

Socrates’ Image, Encyclopaedia Britannica, Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc., Accessed November 11, 2018.

Taylor, A. E. Socrates. Boston: The Beacon Press, 1951. This work is in the Public Domain.